[go: up one dir, main page]

In mathematics, a Vitali set is an elementary example of a set of real numbers that is not Lebesgue measurable, found by Giuseppe Vitali in 1905.[1] The Vitali theorem is the existence theorem that there are such sets. Each Vitali set is uncountable, and there are uncountably many Vitali sets. The proof of their existence depends on the axiom of choice.

Measurable sets

edit

Certain sets have a definite 'length' or 'mass'. For instance, the interval [0, 1] is deemed to have length 1; more generally, an interval [a, b], ab, is deemed to have length b − a. If we think of such intervals as metal rods with uniform density, they likewise have well-defined masses. The set [0, 1] ∪ [2, 3] is composed of two intervals of length one, so we take its total length to be 2. In terms of mass, we have two rods of mass 1, so the total mass is 2.

There is a natural question here: if E is an arbitrary subset of the real line, does it have a 'mass' or 'total length'? As an example, we might ask what is the mass of the set of rational numbers between 0 and 1, given that the mass of the interval [0, 1] is 1. The rationals are dense in the reals, so any value between and including 0 and 1 may appear reasonable.

However the closest generalization to mass is sigma additivity, which gives rise to the Lebesgue measure. It assigns a measure of ba to the interval [a, b], but will assign a measure of 0 to the set of rational numbers because it is countable. Any set which has a well-defined Lebesgue measure is said to be "measurable", but the construction of the Lebesgue measure (for instance using Carathéodory's extension theorem) does not make it obvious whether non-measurable sets exist. The answer to that question involves the axiom of choice.

Construction and proof

edit

A Vitali set is a subset   of the interval   of real numbers such that, for each real number  , there is exactly one number   such that   is a rational number. Vitali sets exist because the rational numbers   form a normal subgroup of the real numbers   under addition, and this allows the construction of the additive quotient group   of these two groups which is the group formed by the cosets   of the rational numbers as a subgroup of the real numbers under addition. This group   consists of disjoint "shifted copies" of   in the sense that each element of this quotient group is a set of the form   for some   in  . The uncountably many elements of   partition   into disjoint sets, and each element is dense in  . Each element of   intersects  , and the axiom of choice guarantees the existence of a subset of   containing exactly one representative out of each element of  . A set formed this way is called a Vitali set.

Every Vitali set   is uncountable, and   is irrational for any  .

Non-measurability

edit
 
A possible enumeration of the positive rational numbers

A Vitali set is non-measurable. To show this, we assume that   is measurable and we derive a contradiction. Let   be an enumeration of the rational numbers in   (recall that the rational numbers are countable). From the construction of  , we can show that the translated sets  ,   are pairwise disjoint. (If not, then there exists distinct   and   such that  , a contradiction.)

Next, note that

 

To see the first inclusion, consider any real number   in   and let   be the representative in   for the equivalence class  ; then   for some rational number   in   which implies that   is in  .

Apply the Lebesgue measure to these inclusions using sigma additivity:

 

Because the Lebesgue measure is translation invariant,   and therefore

 

But this is impossible. Summing infinitely many copies of the constant   yields either zero or infinity, according to whether the constant is zero or positive. In neither case is the sum in  . So   cannot have been measurable after all, i.e., the Lebesgue measure   must not define any value for  .

Properties

edit

No Vitali set has the property of Baire.[2]

By modifying the above proof, one shows that each Vitali set has Banach measure 0. This does not create any contradictions since Banach measures are not countably additive, but only finitely additive.

Role of the axiom of choice

edit

The construction of Vitali sets given above uses the axiom of choice. The question arises: is the axiom of choice needed to prove the existence of sets that are not Lebesgue measurable? The answer is yes, provided that inaccessible cardinals are consistent with the most common axiomatization of set theory, so-called ZFC.

In 1964, Robert Solovay constructed a model of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice where all sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. This is known as the Solovay model.[3] In his proof, Solovay assumed that the existence of inaccessible cardinals is consistent with the other axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, i.e. that it creates no contradictions. This assumption is widely believed to be true by set theorists, but it cannot be proven in ZFC alone.[4]

In 1980, Saharon Shelah proved that it is not possible to establish Solovay's result without his assumption on inaccessible cardinals.[4]

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ Vitali, Giuseppe (1905). "Sul problema della misura dei gruppi di punti di una retta". Bologna, Tip. Gamberini e Parmeggiani.
  2. ^ Oxtoby, John C. (1980), Measure and Category, Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 2 (2nd ed.), Springer-Verlag, ISBN 978-0-387-90508-2. See page 22.
  3. ^ Solovay, Robert M. (1970), "A model of set-theory in which every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable", Annals of Mathematics, Second Series, 92 (1): 1–56, doi:10.2307/1970696, ISSN 0003-486X, JSTOR 1970696, MR 0265151
  4. ^ a b Wagon, Stan; Tomkowicz, Grzegorz (2016). The Banach-Tarski Paradox (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 296–299.

Bibliography

edit