[go: up one dir, main page]

The uncertainty principle, also known as Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position and momentum, can be simultaneously known. In other words, the more accurately one property is measured, the less accurately the other property can be known.

Canonical commutation rule for position q and momentum p variables of a particle, 1927. pqqp = h/(2πi). Uncertainty principle of Heisenberg, 1927.

More formally, the uncertainty principle is any of a variety of mathematical inequalities asserting a fundamental limit to the product of the accuracy of certain related pairs of measurements on a quantum system, such as position, x, and momentum, p.[1] Such paired-variables are known as complementary variables or canonically conjugate variables.

First introduced in 1927 by German physicist Werner Heisenberg,[2][3][4][5] the formal inequality relating the standard deviation of position σx and the standard deviation of momentum σp was derived by Earle Hesse Kennard[6] later that year and by Hermann Weyl[7] in 1928:

where is the reduced Planck constant.

The quintessentially quantum mechanical uncertainty principle comes in many forms other than position–momentum. The energy–time relationship is widely used to relate quantum state lifetime to measured energy widths but its formal derivation is fraught with confusing issues about the nature of time. The basic principle has been extended in numerous directions; it must be considered in many kinds of fundamental physical measurements.

Position-momentum

edit
 
The superposition of several plane waves to form a wave packet. This wave packet becomes increasingly localized with the addition of many waves. The Fourier transform is a mathematical operation that separates a wave packet into its individual plane waves. The waves shown here are real for illustrative purposes only; in quantum mechanics the wave function is generally complex.

It is vital to illustrate how the principle applies to relatively intelligible physical situations since it is indiscernible on the macroscopic[8] scales that humans experience. Two alternative frameworks for quantum physics offer different explanations for the uncertainty principle. The wave mechanics picture of the uncertainty principle is more visually intuitive, but the more abstract matrix mechanics picture formulates it in a way that generalizes more easily.

Mathematically, in wave mechanics, the uncertainty relation between position and momentum arises because the expressions of the wavefunction in the two corresponding orthonormal bases in Hilbert space are Fourier transforms of one another (i.e., position and momentum are conjugate variables). A nonzero function and its Fourier transform cannot both be sharply localized at the same time.[9] A similar tradeoff between the variances of Fourier conjugates arises in all systems underlain by Fourier analysis, for example in sound waves: A pure tone is a sharp spike at a single frequency, while its Fourier transform gives the shape of the sound wave in the time domain, which is a completely delocalized sine wave. In quantum mechanics, the two key points are that the position of the particle takes the form of a matter wave, and momentum is its Fourier conjugate, assured by the de Broglie relation p = ħk, where k is the wavenumber.

In matrix mechanics, the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics, any pair of non-commuting self-adjoint operators representing observables are subject to similar uncertainty limits. An eigenstate of an observable represents the state of the wavefunction for a certain measurement value (the eigenvalue). For example, if a measurement of an observable A is performed, then the system is in a particular eigenstate Ψ of that observable. However, the particular eigenstate of the observable A need not be an eigenstate of another observable B: If so, then it does not have a unique associated measurement for it, as the system is not in an eigenstate of that observable.[10]

Visualization

edit

The uncertainty principle can be visualized using the position- and momentum-space wavefunctions for one spinless particle with mass in one dimension.

The more localized the position-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with the position coordinates in that region, and correspondingly the momentum-space wavefunction is less localized so the possible momentum components the particle could have are more widespread. Conversely, the more localized the momentum-space wavefunction, the more likely the particle is to be found with those values of momentum components in that region, and correspondingly the less localized the position-space wavefunction, so the position coordinates the particle could occupy are more widespread. These wavefunctions are Fourier transforms of each other: mathematically, the uncertainty principle expresses the relationship between conjugate variables in the transform.

 
Position x and momentum p wavefunctions corresponding to quantum particles. The colour opacity of the particles corresponds to the probability density of finding the particle with position x or momentum component p.
Top: If wavelength λ is unknown, so are momentum p, wave-vector k and energy E (de Broglie relations). As the particle is more localized in position space, Δx is smaller than for Δpx.
Bottom: If λ is known, so are p, k, and E. As the particle is more localized in momentum space, Δp is smaller than for Δx.

Wave mechanics interpretation

edit
Propagation of de Broglie waves in 1d—real part of the complex amplitude is blue, imaginary part is green. The probability (shown as the colour opacity) of finding the particle at a given point x is spread out like a waveform, there is no definite position of the particle. As the amplitude increases above zero the curvature reverses sign, so the amplitude begins to decrease again, and vice versa—the result is an alternating amplitude: a wave.

According to the de Broglie hypothesis, every object in the universe is associated with a wave. Thus every object, from an elementary particle to atoms, molecules and on up to planets and beyond are subject to the uncertainty principle.

The time-independent wave function of a single-moded plane wave of wavenumber k0 or momentum p0 is[11]  

The Born rule states that this should be interpreted as a probability density amplitude function in the sense that the probability of finding the particle between a and b is  

In the case of the single-mode plane wave,   is 1 if   and 0 otherwise. In other words, the particle position is extremely uncertain in the sense that it could be essentially anywhere along the wave packet.

On the other hand, consider a wave function that is a sum of many waves, which we may write as   where An represents the relative contribution of the mode pn to the overall total. The figures to the right show how with the addition of many plane waves, the wave packet can become more localized. We may take this a step further to the continuum limit, where the wave function is an integral over all possible modes   with   representing the amplitude of these modes and is called the wave function in momentum space. In mathematical terms, we say that   is the Fourier transform of   and that x and p are conjugate variables. Adding together all of these plane waves comes at a cost, namely the momentum has become less precise, having become a mixture of waves of many different momenta.[12]

One way to quantify the precision of the position and momentum is the standard deviation σ. Since   is a probability density function for position, we calculate its standard deviation.

The precision of the position is improved, i.e. reduced σx, by using many plane waves, thereby weakening the precision of the momentum, i.e. increased σp. Another way of stating this is that σx and σp have an inverse relationship or are at least bounded from below. This is the uncertainty principle, the exact limit of which is the Kennard bound.

Proof of the Kennard inequality using wave mechanics

edit

We are interested in the variances of position and momentum, defined as    

Without loss of generality, we will assume that the means vanish, which just amounts to a shift of the origin of our coordinates. (A more general proof that does not make this assumption is given below.) This gives us the simpler form    

The function   can be interpreted as a vector in a function space. We can define an inner product for a pair of functions u(x) and v(x) in this vector space:   where the asterisk denotes the complex conjugate.

With this inner product defined, we note that the variance for position can be written as  

We can repeat this for momentum by interpreting the function   as a vector, but we can also take advantage of the fact that   and   are Fourier transforms of each other. We evaluate the inverse Fourier transform through integration by parts:   where   in the integration by parts, the cancelled term vanishes because the wave function vanishes at infinity, and the final two integrations re-assert the Fourier transforms. Often the term   is called the momentum operator in position space. Applying Plancherel's theorem and then Parseval's theorem, we see that the variance for momentum can be written as  

The Cauchy–Schwarz inequality asserts that  

The modulus squared of any complex number z can be expressed as   we let   and   and substitute these into the equation above to get  

All that remains is to evaluate these inner products.

 

Plugging this into the above inequalities, we get   or taking the square root  

with equality if and only if p and x are linearly dependent. Note that the only physics involved in this proof was that   and   are wave functions for position and momentum, which are Fourier transforms of each other. A similar result would hold for any pair of conjugate variables.

Matrix mechanics interpretation

edit

In matrix mechanics, observables such as position and momentum are represented by self-adjoint operators.[12] When considering pairs of observables, an important quantity is the commutator. For a pair of operators  and  , one defines their commutator as   In the case of position and momentum, the commutator is the canonical commutation relation  

The physical meaning of the non-commutativity can be understood by considering the effect of the commutator on position and momentum eigenstates. Let   be a right eigenstate of position with a constant eigenvalue x0. By definition, this means that   Applying the commutator to   yields   where Î is the identity operator.

Suppose, for the sake of proof by contradiction, that   is also a right eigenstate of momentum, with constant eigenvalue p0. If this were true, then one could write   On the other hand, the above canonical commutation relation requires that   This implies that no quantum state can simultaneously be both a position and a momentum eigenstate.

When a state is measured, it is projected onto an eigenstate in the basis of the relevant observable. For example, if a particle's position is measured, then the state amounts to a position eigenstate. This means that the state is not a momentum eigenstate, however, but rather it can be represented as a sum of multiple momentum basis eigenstates. In other words, the momentum must be less precise. This precision may be quantified by the standard deviations,    

As in the wave mechanics interpretation above, one sees a tradeoff between the respective precisions of the two, quantified by the uncertainty principle.

Quantum harmonic oscillator stationary states

edit

Consider a one-dimensional quantum harmonic oscillator. It is possible to express the position and momentum operators in terms of the creation and annihilation operators:    

Using the standard rules for creation and annihilation operators on the energy eigenstates,     the variances may be computed directly,     The product of these standard deviations is then  

In particular, the above Kennard bound[6] is saturated for the ground state n=0, for which the probability density is just the normal distribution.

Quantum harmonic oscillators with Gaussian initial condition

edit
Position (blue) and momentum (red) probability densities for an initial Gaussian distribution. From top to bottom, the animations show the cases Ω = ω, Ω = 2ω, and Ω = ω/2. Note the tradeoff between the widths of the distributions.

In a quantum harmonic oscillator of characteristic angular frequency ω, place a state that is offset from the bottom of the potential by some displacement x0 as   where Ω describes the width of the initial state but need not be the same as ω. Through integration over the propagator, we can solve for the full time-dependent solution. After many cancelations, the probability densities reduce to     where we have used the notation   to denote a normal distribution of mean μ and variance σ2. Copying the variances above and applying trigonometric identities, we can write the product of the standard deviations as  

From the relations   we can conclude the following (the right most equality holds only when Ω = ω):  

Coherent states

edit

A coherent state is a right eigenstate of the annihilation operator,   which may be represented in terms of Fock states as  

In the picture where the coherent state is a massive particle in a quantum harmonic oscillator, the position and momentum operators may be expressed in terms of the annihilation operators in the same formulas above and used to calculate the variances,     Therefore, every coherent state saturates the Kennard bound   with position and momentum each contributing an amount   in a "balanced" way. Moreover, every squeezed coherent state also saturates the Kennard bound although the individual contributions of position and momentum need not be balanced in general.

Particle in a box

edit

Consider a particle in a one-dimensional box of length  . The eigenfunctions in position and momentum space are   and   where   and we have used the de Broglie relation  . The variances of   and   can be calculated explicitly:    

The product of the standard deviations is therefore   For all  , the quantity   is greater than 1, so the uncertainty principle is never violated. For numerical concreteness, the smallest value occurs when  , in which case  

Constant momentum

edit
 
Position space probability density of an initially Gaussian state moving at minimally uncertain, constant momentum in free space

Assume a particle initially has a momentum space wave function described by a normal distribution around some constant momentum p0 according to   where we have introduced a reference scale  , with   describing the width of the distribution—cf. nondimensionalization. If the state is allowed to evolve in free space, then the time-dependent momentum and position space wave functions are    

Since   and  , this can be interpreted as a particle moving along with constant momentum at arbitrarily high precision. On the other hand, the standard deviation of the position is   such that the uncertainty product can only increase with time as  

Mathematical formalism

edit

Starting with Kennard's derivation of position-momentum uncertainty, Howard Percy Robertson developed[13][1] a formulation for arbitrary Hermitian operator operators   expressed in terms of their standard deviation   where the brackets   indicate an expectation value of the observable represented by operator  . For a pair of operators   and  , define their commutator as  

and the Robertson uncertainty relation is given by[14]  

Erwin Schrödinger[15] showed how to allow for correlation between the operators, giving a stronger inequality, known as the Robertson-Schrödinger uncertainty relation,[16][1]

 

where the anticommutator,   is used.

Proof of the Schrödinger uncertainty relation

The derivation shown here incorporates and builds off of those shown in Robertson,[13] Schrödinger[16] and standard textbooks such as Griffiths.[17]: 138  For any Hermitian operator  , based upon the definition of variance, we have   we let   and thus  

Similarly, for any other Hermitian operator   in the same state   for  

The product of the two deviations can thus be expressed as

  (1)

In order to relate the two vectors   and  , we use the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality[18] which is defined as   and thus Equation (1) can be written as

  (2)

Since   is in general a complex number, we use the fact that the modulus squared of any complex number   is defined as  , where   is the complex conjugate of  . The modulus squared can also be expressed as

  (3)

we let   and   and substitute these into the equation above to get

  (4)

The inner product   is written out explicitly as   and using the fact that   and   are Hermitian operators, we find  

Similarly it can be shown that  

Thus, we have   and  

We now substitute the above two equations above back into Eq. (4) and get  

Substituting the above into Equation (2) we get the Schrödinger uncertainty relation  

This proof has an issue[19] related to the domains of the operators involved. For the proof to make sense, the vector   has to be in the domain of the unbounded operator  , which is not always the case. In fact, the Robertson uncertainty relation is false if   is an angle variable and   is the derivative with respect to this variable. In this example, the commutator is a nonzero constant—just as in the Heisenberg uncertainty relation—and yet there are states where the product of the uncertainties is zero.[20] (See the counterexample section below.) This issue can be overcome by using a variational method for the proof,[21][22] or by working with an exponentiated version of the canonical commutation relations.[20]

Note that in the general form of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation, there is no need to assume that the operators   and   are self-adjoint operators. It suffices to assume that they are merely symmetric operators. (The distinction between these two notions is generally glossed over in the physics literature, where the term Hermitian is used for either or both classes of operators. See Chapter 9 of Hall's book[23] for a detailed discussion of this important but technical distinction.)

Phase space

edit

In the phase space formulation of quantum mechanics, the Robertson–Schrödinger relation follows from a positivity condition on a real star-square function. Given a Wigner function   with star product ★ and a function f, the following is generally true:[24]  

Choosing  , we arrive at  

Since this positivity condition is true for all a, b, and c, it follows that all the eigenvalues of the matrix are non-negative.

The non-negative eigenvalues then imply a corresponding non-negativity condition on the determinant,   or, explicitly, after algebraic manipulation,  

Examples

edit

Since the Robertson and Schrödinger relations are for general operators, the relations can be applied to any two observables to obtain specific uncertainty relations. A few of the most common relations found in the literature are given below.

  • Position–linear momentum uncertainty relation: for the position and linear momentum operators, the canonical commutation relation   implies the Kennard inequality from above:  
  • Angular momentum uncertainty relation: For two orthogonal components of the total angular momentum operator of an object:   where i, j, k are distinct, and Ji denotes angular momentum along the xi axis. This relation implies that unless all three components vanish together, only a single component of a system's angular momentum can be defined with arbitrary precision, normally the component parallel to an external (magnetic or electric) field. Moreover, for  , a choice  ,  , in angular momentum multiplets, ψ = |j, m⟩, bounds the Casimir invariant (angular momentum squared,  ) from below and thus yields useful constraints such as j(j + 1) ≥ m(m + 1), and hence jm, among others.

Limitations

edit

The derivation of the Robertson inequality for operators   and   requires   and   to be defined. There are quantum systems where these conditions are not valid.[27] One example is a quantum particle on a ring, where the wave function depends on an angular variable   in the interval  . Define "position" and "momentum" operators   and   by   and   with periodic boundary conditions on  . The definition of   depends the   range from 0 to  . These operators satisfy the usual commutation relations for position and momentum operators,  . More precisely,   whenever both   and   are defined, and the space of such   is a dense subspace of the quantum Hilbert space.[28]

Now let   be any of the eigenstates of  , which are given by  . These states are normalizable, unlike the eigenstates of the momentum operator on the line. Also the operator   is bounded, since   ranges over a bounded interval. Thus, in the state  , the uncertainty of   is zero and the uncertainty of   is finite, so that   The Robertson uncertainty principle does not apply in this case:   is not in the domain of the operator  , since multiplication by   disrupts the periodic boundary conditions imposed on  .[20]

For the usual position and momentum operators   and   on the real line, no such counterexamples can occur. As long as   and   are defined in the state  , the Heisenberg uncertainty principle holds, even if   fails to be in the domain of   or of  .[29]

Mixed states

edit

The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty can be improved noting that it must hold for all components   in any decomposition of the density matrix given as   Here, for the probabilities   and   hold. Then, using the relation   for  , it follows that[30]   where the function in the bound is defined   The above relation very often has a bound larger than that of the original Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation. Thus, we need to calculate the bound of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty for the mixed components of the quantum state rather than for the quantum state, and compute an average of their square roots. The following expression is stronger than the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation   where on the right-hand side there is a concave roof over the decompositions of the density matrix. The improved relation above is saturated by all single-qubit quantum states.[30]

With similar arguments, one can derive a relation with a convex roof on the right-hand side[30]   where   denotes the quantum Fisher information and the density matrix is decomposed to pure states as   The derivation takes advantage of the fact that the quantum Fisher information is the convex roof of the variance times four.[31][32]

A simpler inequality follows without a convex roof[33]   which is stronger than the Heisenberg uncertainty relation, since for the quantum Fisher information we have   while for pure states the equality holds.

The Maccone–Pati uncertainty relations

edit

The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty relation can be trivial if the state of the system is chosen to be eigenstate of one of the observable. The stronger uncertainty relations proved by Lorenzo Maccone and Arun K. Pati give non-trivial bounds on the sum of the variances for two incompatible observables.[34] (Earlier works on uncertainty relations formulated as the sum of variances include, e.g., Ref.[35] due to Yichen Huang.) For two non-commuting observables   and   the first stronger uncertainty relation is given by   where  ,  ,   is a normalized vector that is orthogonal to the state of the system   and one should choose the sign of   to make this real quantity a positive number.

The second stronger uncertainty relation is given by   where   is a state orthogonal to  . The form of   implies that the right-hand side of the new uncertainty relation is nonzero unless   is an eigenstate of  . One may note that   can be an eigenstate of   without being an eigenstate of either   or  . However, when   is an eigenstate of one of the two observables the Heisenberg–Schrödinger uncertainty relation becomes trivial. But the lower bound in the new relation is nonzero unless   is an eigenstate of both.

Energy–time

edit

An energy–time uncertainty relation like   has a long, controversial history; the meaning of   and   varies and different formulations have different arenas of validity.[36] However, one well-known application is both well established[37][38] and experimentally verified:[39][40] the connection between the life-time of a resonance state,   and its energy width  :   In particle-physics, widths from experimental fits to the Breit–Wigner energy distribution are used to characterize the lifetime of quasi-stable or decaying states.[41]

An informal, heuristic meaning of the principle is the following:[42] A state that only exists for a short time cannot have a definite energy. To have a definite energy, the frequency of the state must be defined accurately, and this requires the state to hang around for many cycles, the reciprocal of the required accuracy. For example, in spectroscopy, excited states have a finite lifetime. By the time–energy uncertainty principle, they do not have a definite energy, and, each time they decay, the energy they release is slightly different. The average energy of the outgoing photon has a peak at the theoretical energy of the state, but the distribution has a finite width called the natural linewidth. Fast-decaying states have a broad linewidth, while slow-decaying states have a narrow linewidth.[43] The same linewidth effect also makes it difficult to specify the rest mass of unstable, fast-decaying particles in particle physics. The faster the particle decays (the shorter its lifetime), the less certain is its mass (the larger the particle's width).

Time in quantum mechanics

edit

The concept of "time" in quantum mechanics offers many challenges.[44] There is no quantum theory of time measurement; relativity is both fundamental to time and difficult to include in quantum mechanics.[36] While position and momentum are associated with a single particle, time is a system property: it has no operator needed for the Robertson–Schrödinger relation.[1] The mathematical treatment of stable and unstable quantum systems differ.[45] These factors combine to make energy–time uncertainty principles controversial.

Three notions of "time" can be distinguished:[36] external, intrinsic, and observable. External or laboratory time is seen by the experimenter; intrinsic time is inferred by changes in dynamic variables, like the hands of a clock or the motion of a free particle; observable time concerns time as an observable, the measurement of time-separated events.

An external-time energy–time uncertainty principle might say that measuring the energy of a quantum system to an accuracy   requires a time interval  .[38] However, Yakir Aharonov and David Bohm[46][36] have shown that, in some quantum systems, energy can be measured accurately within an arbitrarily short time: external-time uncertainty principles are not universal.

Intrinsic time is the basis for several formulations of energy–time uncertainty relations, including the Mandelstam–Tamm relation discussed in the next section. A physical system with an intrinsic time closely matching the external laboratory time is called a "clock".[44]: 31 

Observable time, measuring time between two events, remains a challenge for quantum theories; some progress has been made using positive operator-valued measure concepts.[36]

Mandelstam–Tamm

edit

In 1945, Leonid Mandelstam and Igor Tamm derived a non-relativistic time–energy uncertainty relation as follows.[47][36] From Heisenberg mechanics, the generalized Ehrenfest theorem for an observable B without explicit time dependence, represented by a self-adjoint operator   relates time dependence of the average value of   to the average of its commutator with the Hamiltonian:

 

The value of   is then substituted in the Robertson uncertainty relation for the energy operator   and  :   giving   (whenever the denominator is nonzero). While this is a universal result, it depends upon the observable chosen and that the deviations   and   are computed for a particular state. Identifying   and the characteristic time   gives an energy–time relationship   Although   has the dimension of time, it is different from the time parameter t that enters the Schrödinger equation. This   can be interpreted as time for which the expectation value of the observable,   changes by an amount equal to one standard deviation.[48] Examples:

  • The time a free quantum particle passes a point in space is more uncertain as the energy of the state is more precisely controlled:   Since the time spread is related to the particle position spread and the energy spread is related to the momentum spread, this relation is directly related to position–momentum uncertainty.[17]: 144 
  • A Delta particle, a quasistable composite of quarks related to protons and neutrons, has a lifetime of 10−23 s, so its measured mass equivalent to energy, 1232 MeV/c2, varies by ±120 MeV/c2; this variation is intrinsic and not caused by measurement errors.[17]: 144 
  • Two energy states   with energies   superimposed to create a composite state
 
The probability amplitude of this state has a time-dependent interference term:
 
The oscillation period varies inversely with the energy difference:  .[17]: 144 

Each example has a different meaning for the time uncertainty, according to the observable and state used.

Quantum field theory

edit

Some formulations of quantum field theory uses temporary electron–positron pairs in its calculations called virtual particles. The mass-energy and lifetime of these particles are related by the energy–time uncertainty relation. The energy of a quantum systems is not known with enough precision to limit their behavior to a single, simple history. Thus the influence of all histories must be incorporated into quantum calculations, including those with much greater or much less energy than the mean of the measured/calculated energy distribution.

The energy–time uncertainty principle does not temporarily violate conservation of energy; it does not imply that energy can be "borrowed" from the universe as long as it is "returned" within a short amount of time.[17]: 145  The energy of the universe is not an exactly known parameter at all times.[1] When events transpire at very short time intervals, there is uncertainty in the energy of these events.

Harmonic analysis

edit

In the context of harmonic analysis the uncertainty principle implies that one cannot at the same time localize the value of a function and its Fourier transform. To wit, the following inequality holds,  

Further mathematical uncertainty inequalities, including the above entropic uncertainty, hold between a function f and its Fourier transform ƒ̂:[49][50][51]  

Signal processing

edit

In the context of time–frequency analysis uncertainty principles are referred to as the Gabor limit, after Dennis Gabor, or sometimes the Heisenberg–Gabor limit. The basic result, which follows from "Benedicks's theorem", below, is that a function cannot be both time limited and band limited (a function and its Fourier transform cannot both have bounded domain)—see bandlimited versus timelimited. More accurately, the time-bandwidth or duration-bandwidth product satisfies   where   and   are the standard deviations of the time and frequency energy concentrations respectively.[52] The minimum is attained for a Gaussian-shaped pulse (Gabor wavelet) [For the un-squared Gaussian (i.e. signal amplitude) and its un-squared Fourier transform magnitude  ; squaring reduces each   by a factor  .] Another common measure is the product of the time and frequency full width at half maximum (of the power/energy), which for the Gaussian equals   (see bandwidth-limited pulse).

Stated differently, one cannot simultaneously sharply localize a signal f in both the time domain and frequency domain.

When applied to filters, the result implies that one cannot simultaneously achieve a high temporal resolution and high frequency resolution at the same time; a concrete example are the resolution issues of the short-time Fourier transform—if one uses a wide window, one achieves good frequency resolution at the cost of temporal resolution, while a narrow window has the opposite trade-off.

Alternate theorems give more precise quantitative results, and, in time–frequency analysis, rather than interpreting the (1-dimensional) time and frequency domains separately, one instead interprets the limit as a lower limit on the support of a function in the (2-dimensional) time–frequency plane. In practice, the Gabor limit limits the simultaneous time–frequency resolution one can achieve without interference; it is possible to achieve higher resolution, but at the cost of different components of the signal interfering with each other.

As a result, in order to analyze signals where the transients are important, the wavelet transform is often used instead of the Fourier.

Discrete Fourier transform

edit

Let   be a sequence of N complex numbers and   be its discrete Fourier transform.

Denote by   the number of non-zero elements in the time sequence   and by   the number of non-zero elements in the frequency sequence  . Then,  

This inequality is sharp, with equality achieved when x or X is a Dirac mass, or more generally when x is a nonzero multiple of a Dirac comb supported on a subgroup of the integers modulo N (in which case X is also a Dirac comb supported on a complementary subgroup, and vice versa).

More generally, if T and W are subsets of the integers modulo N, let   denote the time-limiting operator and band-limiting operators, respectively. Then   where the norm is the operator norm of operators on the Hilbert space   of functions on the integers modulo N. This inequality has implications for signal reconstruction.[53]

When N is a prime number, a stronger inequality holds:   Discovered by Terence Tao, this inequality is also sharp.[54]

Benedicks's theorem

edit

Amrein–Berthier[55] and Benedicks's theorem[56] intuitively says that the set of points where f is non-zero and the set of points where ƒ̂ is non-zero cannot both be small.

Specifically, it is impossible for a function f in L2(R) and its Fourier transform ƒ̂ to both be supported on sets of finite Lebesgue measure. A more quantitative version is[57][58]  

One expects that the factor CeC|S||Σ| may be replaced by CeC(|S||Σ|)1/d, which is only known if either S or Σ is convex.

Hardy's uncertainty principle

edit

The mathematician G. H. Hardy formulated the following uncertainty principle:[59] it is not possible for f and ƒ̂ to both be "very rapidly decreasing". Specifically, if f in   is such that   and   (  an integer), then, if ab > 1, f = 0, while if ab = 1, then there is a polynomial P of degree N such that  

This was later improved as follows: if   is such that   then   where P is a polynomial of degree (Nd)/2 and A is a real d × d positive definite matrix.

This result was stated in Beurling's complete works without proof and proved in Hörmander[60] (the case  ) and Bonami, Demange, and Jaming[61] for the general case. Note that Hörmander–Beurling's version implies the case ab > 1 in Hardy's Theorem while the version by Bonami–Demange–Jaming covers the full strength of Hardy's Theorem. A different proof of Beurling's theorem based on Liouville's theorem appeared in ref.[62]

A full description of the case ab < 1 as well as the following extension to Schwartz class distributions appears in ref.[63]

Theorem —  If a tempered distribution   is such that   and   then   for some convenient polynomial P and real positive definite matrix A of type d × d.

Additional uncertainty relations

edit

Heisenberg limit

edit

In quantum metrology, and especially interferometry, the Heisenberg limit is the optimal rate at which the accuracy of a measurement can scale with the energy used in the measurement. Typically, this is the measurement of a phase (applied to one arm of a beam-splitter) and the energy is given by the number of photons used in an interferometer. Although some claim to have broken the Heisenberg limit, this reflects disagreement on the definition of the scaling resource.[64] Suitably defined, the Heisenberg limit is a consequence of the basic principles of quantum mechanics and cannot be beaten, although the weak Heisenberg limit can be beaten.[65]

Systematic and statistical errors

edit

The inequalities above focus on the statistical imprecision of observables as quantified by the standard deviation  . Heisenberg's original version, however, was dealing with the systematic error, a disturbance of the quantum system produced by the measuring apparatus, i.e., an observer effect.

If we let   represent the error (i.e., inaccuracy) of a measurement of an observable A and   the disturbance produced on a subsequent measurement of the conjugate variable B by the former measurement of A, then the inequality proposed by Masanao Ozawa − encompassing both systematic and statistical errors - holds:[66]

 

Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, as originally described in the 1927 formulation, mentions only the first term of Ozawa inequality, regarding the systematic error. Using the notation above to describe the error/disturbance effect of sequential measurements (first A, then B), it could be written as

 

The formal derivation of the Heisenberg relation is possible but far from intuitive. It was not proposed by Heisenberg, but formulated in a mathematically consistent way only in recent years.[67][68] Also, it must be stressed that the Heisenberg formulation is not taking into account the intrinsic statistical errors   and  . There is increasing experimental evidence[69][70][71][72] that the total quantum uncertainty cannot be described by the Heisenberg term alone, but requires the presence of all the three terms of the Ozawa inequality.

Using the same formalism,[1] it is also possible to introduce the other kind of physical situation, often confused with the previous one, namely the case of simultaneous measurements (A and B at the same time):

 

The two simultaneous measurements on A and B are necessarily[73] unsharp or weak.

It is also possible to derive an uncertainty relation that, as the Ozawa's one, combines both the statistical and systematic error components, but keeps a form very close to the Heisenberg original inequality. By adding Robertson[1]

 

and Ozawa relations we obtain   The four terms can be written as:   Defining:   as the inaccuracy in the measured values of the variable A and   as the resulting fluctuation in the conjugate variable B, Kazuo Fujikawa[74] established an uncertainty relation similar to the Heisenberg original one, but valid both for systematic and statistical errors:

 

Quantum entropic uncertainty principle

edit

For many distributions, the standard deviation is not a particularly natural way of quantifying the structure. For example, uncertainty relations in which one of the observables is an angle has little physical meaning for fluctuations larger than one period.[22][75][76][77] Other examples include highly bimodal distributions, or unimodal distributions with divergent variance.

A solution that overcomes these issues is an uncertainty based on entropic uncertainty instead of the product of variances. While formulating the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics in 1957, Hugh Everett III conjectured a stronger extension of the uncertainty principle based on entropic certainty.[78] This conjecture, also studied by I. I. Hirschman[79] and proven in 1975 by W. Beckner[80] and by Iwo Bialynicki-Birula and Jerzy Mycielski[81] is that, for two normalized, dimensionless Fourier transform pairs f(a) and g(b) where

     and      

the Shannon information entropies   and   are subject to the following constraint,

 

where the logarithms may be in any base.

The probability distribution functions associated with the position wave function ψ(x) and the momentum wave function φ(x) have dimensions of inverse length and momentum respectively, but the entropies may be rendered dimensionless by     where x0 and p0 are some arbitrarily chosen length and momentum respectively, which render the arguments of the logarithms dimensionless. Note that the entropies will be functions of these chosen parameters. Due to the Fourier transform relation between the position wave function ψ(x) and the momentum wavefunction φ(p), the above constraint can be written for the corresponding entropies as

 

where h is the Planck constant.

Depending on one's choice of the x0 p0 product, the expression may be written in many ways. If x0 p0 is chosen to be h, then  

If, instead, x0 p0 is chosen to be ħ, then  

If x0 and p0 are chosen to be unity in whatever system of units are being used, then   where h is interpreted as a dimensionless number equal to the value of the Planck constant in the chosen system of units. Note that these inequalities can be extended to multimode quantum states, or wavefunctions in more than one spatial dimension.[82]

The quantum entropic uncertainty principle is more restrictive than the Heisenberg uncertainty principle. From the inverse logarithmic Sobolev inequalities[83]     (equivalently, from the fact that normal distributions maximize the entropy of all such with a given variance), it readily follows that this entropic uncertainty principle is stronger than the one based on standard deviations, because  

In other words, the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, is a consequence of the quantum entropic uncertainty principle, but not vice versa. A few remarks on these inequalities. First, the choice of base e is a matter of popular convention in physics. The logarithm can alternatively be in any base, provided that it be consistent on both sides of the inequality. Second, recall the Shannon entropy has been used, not the quantum von Neumann entropy. Finally, the normal distribution saturates the inequality, and it is the only distribution with this property, because it is the maximum entropy probability distribution among those with fixed variance (cf. here for proof).

A measurement apparatus will have a finite resolution set by the discretization of its possible outputs into bins, with the probability of lying within one of the bins given by the Born rule. We will consider the most common experimental situation, in which the bins are of uniform size. Let δx be a measure of the spatial resolution. We take the zeroth bin to be centered near the origin, with possibly some small constant offset c. The probability of lying within the jth interval of width δx is  

To account for this discretization, we can define the Shannon entropy of the wave function for a given measurement apparatus as  

Under the above definition, the entropic uncertainty relation is  

Here we note that δx δp/h is a typical infinitesimal phase space volume used in the calculation of a partition function. The inequality is also strict and not saturated. Efforts to improve this bound are an active area of research.

Uncertainty relation with three angular momentum components

edit

For a particle of total angular momentum   the following uncertainty relation holds   where   are angular momentum components. The relation can be derived from   and   The relation can be strengthened as[30][84]   where   is the quantum Fisher information.

History

edit

In 1925 Heisenberg published the Umdeutung (reinterpretation) paper where he showed that central aspect of quantum theory was the non-commutativity: the theory implied that the relative order of position and momentum measurement was significant. Working with Max Born and Pascual Jordan, he continued to develop matrix mechanics, that would become the first modern quantum mechanics formulation.[85]

 
Werner Heisenberg and Niels Bohr

In March 1926, working in Bohr's institute, Heisenberg realized that the non-commutativity implies the uncertainty principle. Writing to Wolfgang Pauli in February 1927, he worked out the basic concepts.[86]

In his celebrated 1927 paper "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik" ("On the Perceptual Content of Quantum Theoretical Kinematics and Mechanics"), Heisenberg established this expression as the minimum amount of unavoidable momentum disturbance caused by any position measurement,[2] but he did not give a precise definition for the uncertainties Δx and Δp. Instead, he gave some plausible estimates in each case separately. His paper gave an analysis in terms of a microscope that Bohr showed was incorrect; Heisenberg included an addendum to the publication.

In his 1930 Chicago lecture[87] he refined his principle:

  (A1)

Later work broadened the concept. Any two variables that do not commute cannot be measured simultaneously—the more precisely one is known, the less precisely the other can be known. Heisenberg wrote:

It can be expressed in its simplest form as follows: One can never know with perfect accuracy both of those two important factors which determine the movement of one of the smallest particles—its position and its velocity. It is impossible to determine accurately both the position and the direction and speed of a particle at the same instant.[88]

Kennard[6][1]: 204  in 1927 first proved the modern inequality:

  (A2)

where ħ = h/2π, and σx, σp are the standard deviations of position and momentum. (Heisenberg only proved relation (A2) for the special case of Gaussian states.[87]) In 1929 Robertson generalized the inequality to all observables and in 1930 Schrödinger extended the form to allow non-zero covariance of the operators; this result is referred to as Robertson-Schrödinger inequality.[1]: 204 

Terminology and translation

edit

Throughout the main body of his original 1927 paper, written in German, Heisenberg used the word "Ungenauigkeit",[2] to describe the basic theoretical principle. Only in the endnote did he switch to the word "Unsicherheit". Later on, he always used "Unbestimmtheit". When the English-language version of Heisenberg's textbook, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, was published in 1930, however, only the English word "uncertainty" was used, and it became the term in the English language.[89]

Heisenberg's microscope

edit
 
Heisenberg's gamma-ray microscope for locating an electron (shown in blue). The incoming gamma ray (shown in green) is scattered by the electron up into the microscope's aperture angle θ. The scattered gamma-ray is shown in red. Classical optics shows that the electron position can be resolved only up to an uncertainty Δx that depends on θ and the wavelength λ of the incoming light.

The principle is quite counter-intuitive, so the early students of quantum theory had to be reassured that naive measurements to violate it were bound always to be unworkable. One way in which Heisenberg originally illustrated the intrinsic impossibility of violating the uncertainty principle is by using the observer effect of an imaginary microscope as a measuring device.[87]

He imagines an experimenter trying to measure the position and momentum of an electron by shooting a photon at it.[90]: 49–50 

  • Problem 1 – If the photon has a short wavelength, and therefore, a large momentum, the position can be measured accurately. But the photon scatters in a random direction, transferring a large and uncertain amount of momentum to the electron. If the photon has a long wavelength and low momentum, the collision does not disturb the electron's momentum very much, but the scattering will reveal its position only vaguely.
  • Problem 2 – If a large aperture is used for the microscope, the electron's location can be well resolved (see Rayleigh criterion); but by the principle of conservation of momentum, the transverse momentum of the incoming photon affects the electron's beamline momentum and hence, the new momentum of the electron resolves poorly. If a small aperture is used, the accuracy of both resolutions is the other way around.

The combination of these trade-offs implies that no matter what photon wavelength and aperture size are used, the product of the uncertainty in measured position and measured momentum is greater than or equal to a lower limit, which is (up to a small numerical factor) equal to the Planck constant.[91] Heisenberg did not care to formulate the uncertainty principle as an exact limit, and preferred to use it instead, as a heuristic quantitative statement, correct up to small numerical factors, which makes the radically new noncommutativity of quantum mechanics inevitable.

Intrinsic quantum uncertainty

edit

Historically, the uncertainty principle has been confused[92][66] with a related effect in physics, called the observer effect, which notes that measurements of certain systems cannot be made without affecting the system,[93][94] that is, without changing something in a system. Heisenberg used such an observer effect at the quantum level (see below) as a physical "explanation" of quantum uncertainty.[95] It has since become clearer, however, that the uncertainty principle is inherent in the properties of all wave-like systems,[69] and that it arises in quantum mechanics simply due to the matter wave nature of all quantum objects.[96] Thus, the uncertainty principle actually states a fundamental property of quantum systems and is not a statement about the observational success of current technology.[97]

Critical reactions

edit

The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and Heisenberg's uncertainty principle were, in fact, initially seen as twin targets by detractors. According to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, there is no fundamental reality that the quantum state describes, just a prescription for calculating experimental results. There is no way to say what the state of a system fundamentally is, only what the result of observations might be.

Albert Einstein believed that randomness is a reflection of our ignorance of some fundamental property of reality, while Niels Bohr believed that the probability distributions are fundamental and irreducible, and depend on which measurements we choose to perform. Einstein and Bohr debated the uncertainty principle for many years.

Ideal detached observer

edit

Wolfgang Pauli called Einstein's fundamental objection to the uncertainty principle "the ideal of the detached observer" (phrase translated from the German):

"Like the moon has a definite position" Einstein said to me last winter, "whether or not we look at the moon, the same must also hold for the atomic objects, as there is no sharp distinction possible between these and macroscopic objects. Observation cannot create an element of reality like a position, there must be something contained in the complete description of physical reality which corresponds to the possibility of observing a position, already before the observation has been actually made." I hope, that I quoted Einstein correctly; it is always difficult to quote somebody out of memory with whom one does not agree. It is precisely this kind of postulate which I call the ideal of the detached observer.

— Letter from Pauli to Niels Bohr, February 15, 1955[98]

Einstein's slit

edit

The first of Einstein's thought experiments challenging the uncertainty principle went as follows:

Consider a particle passing through a slit of width d. The slit introduces an uncertainty in momentum of approximately h/d because the particle passes through the wall. But let us determine the momentum of the particle by measuring the recoil of the wall. In doing so, we find the momentum of the particle to arbitrary accuracy by conservation of momentum.

Bohr's response was that the wall is quantum mechanical as well, and that to measure the recoil to accuracy Δp, the momentum of the wall must be known to this accuracy before the particle passes through. This introduces an uncertainty in the position of the wall and therefore the position of the slit equal to h/Δp, and if the wall's momentum is known precisely enough to measure the recoil, the slit's position is uncertain enough to disallow a position measurement.

A similar analysis with particles diffracting through multiple slits is given by Richard Feynman.[99]

Einstein's box

edit

Bohr was present when Einstein proposed the thought experiment which has become known as Einstein's box. Einstein argued that "Heisenberg's uncertainty equation implied that the uncertainty in time was related to the uncertainty in energy, the product of the two being related to the Planck constant."[100] Consider, he said, an ideal box, lined with mirrors so that it can contain light indefinitely. The box could be weighed before a clockwork mechanism opened an ideal shutter at a chosen instant to allow one single photon to escape. "We now know, explained Einstein, precisely the time at which the photon left the box."[101] "Now, weigh the box again. The change of mass tells the energy of the emitted light. In this manner, said Einstein, one could measure the energy emitted and the time it was released with any desired precision, in contradiction to the uncertainty principle."[100]

Bohr spent a sleepless night considering this argument, and eventually realized that it was flawed. He pointed out that if the box were to be weighed, say by a spring and a pointer on a scale, "since the box must move vertically with a change in its weight, there will be uncertainty in its vertical velocity and therefore an uncertainty in its height above the table. ... Furthermore, the uncertainty about the elevation above the Earth's surface will result in an uncertainty in the rate of the clock,"[102] because of Einstein's own theory of gravity's effect on time. "Through this chain of uncertainties, Bohr showed that Einstein's light box experiment could not simultaneously measure exactly both the energy of the photon and the time of its escape."[103]

EPR paradox for entangled particles

edit

In 1935, Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen published an analysis of spatially separated entangled particles (EPR paradox).[104] According to EPR, one could measure the position of one of the entangled particles and the momentum of the second particle, and from those measurements deduce the position and momentum of both particles to any precision, violating the uncertainty principle. In order to avoid such possibility, the measurement of one particle must modify the probability distribution of the other particle instantaneously, possibly violating the principle of locality.[105]

In 1964, John Stewart Bell showed that this assumption can be falsified, since it would imply a certain inequality between the probabilities of different experiments. Experimental results confirm the predictions of quantum mechanics, ruling out EPR's basic assumption of local hidden variables.

Popper's criticism

edit

Science philosopher Karl Popper approached the problem of indeterminacy as a logician and metaphysical realist.[106] He disagreed with the application of the uncertainty relations to individual particles rather than to ensembles of identically prepared particles, referring to them as "statistical scatter relations".[106][107] In this statistical interpretation, a particular measurement may be made to arbitrary precision without invalidating the quantum theory.

In 1934, Popper published Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen (Critique of the Uncertainty Relations) in Naturwissenschaften,[108] and in the same year Logik der Forschung (translated and updated by the author as The Logic of Scientific Discovery in 1959[106]), outlining his arguments for the statistical interpretation. In 1982, he further developed his theory in Quantum theory and the schism in Physics, writing:

[Heisenberg's] formulae are, beyond all doubt, derivable statistical formulae of the quantum theory. But they have been habitually misinterpreted by those quantum theorists who said that these formulae can be interpreted as determining some upper limit to the precision of our measurements. [original emphasis][109]

Popper proposed an experiment to falsify the uncertainty relations, although he later withdrew his initial version after discussions with Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker, Heisenberg, and Einstein; Popper sent his paper to Einstein and it may have influenced the formulation of the EPR paradox.[110]: 720 

Free will

edit

Some scientists including Arthur Compton[111] and Martin Heisenberg[112] have suggested that the uncertainty principle, or at least the general probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics, could be evidence for the two-stage model of free will. One critique, however, is that apart from the basic role of quantum mechanics as a foundation for chemistry, nontrivial biological mechanisms requiring quantum mechanics are unlikely, due to the rapid decoherence time of quantum systems at room temperature.[113] Proponents of this theory commonly say that this decoherence is overcome by both screening and decoherence-free subspaces found in biological cells.[113]

Thermodynamics

edit

There is reason to believe that violating the uncertainty principle also strongly implies the violation of the second law of thermodynamics.[114] See Gibbs paradox.

Rejection of the principle

edit

Uncertainty principles relate quantum particles–electrons for example–to classical concepts–position and momentum. This presumes quantum particles have position and momentum. Edwin C. Kemble pointed out[115] in 1937 that such properties cannot be experimentally verified and assuming they exist gives rise to many contradictions; similarly Rudolf Haag notes that position in quantum mechanics is an attribute of an interaction, say between an electron and a detector, not an intrinsic property.[116][117] From this point of view the uncertainty principle is not a fundamental quantum property but a concept "carried over from the language of our ancestors" as Kemble says.

Applications

edit

Since the uncertainty principle is such a basic result in quantum mechanics, typical experiments in quantum mechanics routinely observe aspects of it. All forms of spectroscopy, including particle physics use the relationship to relate measured energy line-width to the lifetime of quantum states. Certain experiments, however, may deliberately test a particular form of the uncertainty principle as part of their main research program. These include, for example, tests of number–phase uncertainty relations in superconducting[118] or quantum optics[119] systems. Applications dependent on the uncertainty principle for their operation include extremely low-noise technology such as that required in gravitational wave interferometers.[120]


See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i Sen, D. (2014). "The Uncertainty relations in quantum mechanics" (PDF). Current Science. 107 (2): 203–218. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2019-09-24. Retrieved 2016-02-14.
  2. ^ a b c Heisenberg, W. (1927) [1927-03-01]. "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik". Zeitschrift für Physik (in German). 43 (3): 172–198. Bibcode:1927ZPhy...43..172H. doi:10.1007/BF01397280. ISSN 0044-3328. S2CID 122763326.Heisenberg, W (1983) [1927]. "The actual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics". No. NAS 1.15: 77379. 1983. 43 (3–4): 172. Bibcode:1983ZhPhy..43..172H. Archived from the original on 2023-09-02. Retrieved 2023-08-28. English translation of Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik
  3. ^ Werner Heisenberg (1989), Encounters with Einstein and Other Essays on People, Places and Particles, Princeton University Press, p. 53. [ISBN missing]
  4. ^ Dolling, Lisa M.; Gianelli, Arthur F.; Statile, Glenn N., eds. (2003). The Tests of Time. doi:10.1515/9781400889167. ISBN 978-1400889167.
  5. ^ Kumar, Manjit. Quantum: Einstein, Bohr, and the great debate about the nature of reality. 1st American ed., 2008. Chap. 10, Note 37. [ISBN missing]
  6. ^ a b c Kennard, E. H. (1927), "Zur Quantenmechanik einfacher Bewegungstypen", Zeitschrift für Physik (in German), 44 (4–5): 326–352, Bibcode:1927ZPhy...44..326K, doi:10.1007/BF01391200, S2CID 121626384.
  7. ^ Weyl, H. (1928). Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik (in German). Leipzig: Hirzel.[page needed]
  8. ^ Jaeger, Gregg (September 2014). "What in the (quantum) world is macroscopic?". American Journal of Physics. 82 (9): 896–905. Bibcode:2014AmJPh..82..896J. doi:10.1119/1.4878358.
  9. ^ See Appendix B in Bialynicki-Birula, Iwo; Bialynicka-Birula, Zofia (2009), "Why photons cannot be sharply localized", Physical Review A, 79 (3): 7–8, arXiv:0903.3712, Bibcode:2009PhRvA..79c2112B, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.79.032112, S2CID 55632217
  10. ^ Claude Cohen-Tannoudji; Bernard Diu; Franck Laloë (1996), Quantum mechanics, Wiley-Interscience: Wiley, pp. 231–233, ISBN 978-0-471-56952-7
  11. ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 60, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  12. ^ a b Landau, Lev Davidovich; Lifshitz, Evgeny Mikhailovich (1977). Quantum Mechanics: Non-Relativistic Theory. Vol. 3 (3rd ed.). Pergamon Press. ISBN 978-0-08-020940-1.
  13. ^ a b Robertson, H. P. (1929), "The Uncertainty Principle", Phys. Rev., 34 (1): 163–164, Bibcode:1929PhRv...34..163R, doi:10.1103/PhysRev.34.163
  14. ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, pp. 242–243, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  15. ^ Schrödinger, E., Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip, Berliner Berichte, 1930, pp. 296–303.
  16. ^ a b Schrödinger, E. (1930), "Zum Heisenbergschen Unschärfeprinzip", Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse, 14: 296–303
  17. ^ a b c d e Griffiths, David J.; Schroeter, Darrell F. (2018). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press. Bibcode:2018iqm..book.....G. doi:10.1017/9781316995433. ISBN 978-1-316-99543-3. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-27.
  18. ^ Riley, K. F.; M. P. Hobson and S. J. Bence (2006), Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering, Cambridge, p. 246[ISBN missing]
  19. ^ Davidson, E. R. (1965), "On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle", J. Chem. Phys., 42 (4): 1461–1462, Bibcode:1965JChPh..42.1461D, doi:10.1063/1.1696139
  20. ^ a b c Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 245, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  21. ^ Jackiw, Roman (1968), "Minimum Uncertainty Product, Number-Phase Uncertainty Product, and Coherent States", J. Math. Phys., 9 (3): 339–346, Bibcode:1968JMP.....9..339J, doi:10.1063/1.1664585
  22. ^ a b Carruthers, P.; Nieto, M. M. (1968), "Phase and Angle Variables in Quantum Mechanics", Rev. Mod. Phys., 40 (2): 411–440, Bibcode:1968RvMP...40..411C, doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.40.411
  23. ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  24. ^ Curtright, T.; Zachos, C. (2001). "Negative Probability and Uncertainty Relations". Modern Physics Letters A. 16 (37): 2381–2385. arXiv:hep-th/0105226. Bibcode:2001MPLA...16.2381C. doi:10.1142/S021773230100576X. S2CID 119669313.
  25. ^ Likharev, K. K.; A. B. Zorin (1985), "Theory of Bloch-Wave Oscillations in Small Josephson Junctions", J. Low Temp. Phys., 59 (3/4): 347–382, Bibcode:1985JLTP...59..347L, doi:10.1007/BF00683782, S2CID 120813342
  26. ^ Anderson, P. W. (1964), "Special Effects in Superconductivity", in Caianiello, E. R. (ed.), Lectures on the Many-Body Problem, Vol. 2, New York: Academic Press
  27. ^ Davidson, Ernest R. (1965-02-15). "On Derivations of the Uncertainty Principle". The Journal of Chemical Physics. 42 (4): 1461–1462. Bibcode:1965JChPh..42.1461D. doi:10.1063/1.1696139. ISSN 0021-9606. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-20.
  28. ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 245, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  29. ^ Hall, B. C. (2013), Quantum Theory for Mathematicians, Springer, p. 246, Bibcode:2013qtm..book.....H
  30. ^ a b c d Tóth, Géza; Fröwis, Florian (31 January 2022). "Uncertainty relations with the variance and the quantum Fisher information based on convex decompositions of density matrices". Physical Review Research. 4 (1): 013075. arXiv:2109.06893. Bibcode:2022PhRvR...4a3075T. doi:10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013075. S2CID 237513549.
  31. ^ Tóth, Géza; Petz, Dénes (20 March 2013). "Extremal properties of the variance and the quantum Fisher information". Physical Review A. 87 (3): 032324. arXiv:1109.2831. Bibcode:2013PhRvA..87c2324T. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.87.032324. S2CID 55088553.
  32. ^ Yu, Sixia (2013). "Quantum Fisher Information as the Convex Roof of Variance". arXiv:1302.5311 [quant-ph].
  33. ^ Fröwis, Florian; Schmied, Roman; Gisin, Nicolas (2 July 2015). "Tighter quantum uncertainty relations following from a general probabilistic bound". Physical Review A. 92 (1): 012102. arXiv:1409.4440. Bibcode:2015PhRvA..92a2102F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.92.012102. S2CID 58912643.
  34. ^ Maccone, Lorenzo; Pati, Arun K. (31 December 2014). "Stronger Uncertainty Relations for All Incompatible Observables". Physical Review Letters. 113 (26): 260401. arXiv:1407.0338. Bibcode:2014PhRvL.113z0401M. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.113.260401. PMID 25615288. S2CID 21334130.
  35. ^ Huang, Yichen (10 August 2012). "Variance-based uncertainty relations". Physical Review A. 86 (2): 024101. arXiv:1012.3105. Bibcode:2012PhRvA..86b4101H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.86.024101. S2CID 118507388.
  36. ^ a b c d e f Busch, Paul (2002). "The Time-Energy Uncertainty Relation". In Muga, J. G.; Mayato, R. Sala; Egusquiza, I. L. (eds.). Time in Quantum Mechanics. Lecture Notes in Physics. Vol. 72. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 69–98. doi:10.1007/3-540-45846-8_3. ISBN 978-3-540-43294-4.
  37. ^ Wigner, E. P. (1997). "On the Time–Energy Uncertainty Relation". In Wightman, Arthur S. (ed.). Part I: Particles and Fields. Part II: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 538–548. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-09203-3_58. ISBN 978-3-642-08179-8.
  38. ^ a b Hilgevoord, Jan (1996-12-01). "The uncertainty principle for energy and time". American Journal of Physics. 64 (12): 1451–1456. Bibcode:1996AmJPh..64.1451H. doi:10.1119/1.18410. ISSN 0002-9505. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2023-11-12.
  39. ^ Lynch, F. J.; Holland, R. E.; Hamermesh, M. (1960-10-15). "Time Dependence of Resonantly Filtered Gamma Rays from Fe 57". Physical Review. 120 (2): 513–520. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.120.513. ISSN 0031-899X.
  40. ^ Frauenfelder, H. (1962). The Mössbauer Effect. W. A. Benjamin. p. 66. LCCN 61018181.
  41. ^ Bohm, Arno R.; Sato, Yoshihiro (2005-04-28). "Relativistic resonances: Their masses, widths, lifetimes, superposition, and causal evolution". Physical Review D. 71 (8): 085018. arXiv:hep-ph/0412106. Bibcode:2005PhRvD..71h5018B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.71.085018. ISSN 1550-7998. S2CID 119417992.
  42. ^ Karplus, Martin, and Porter, Richard Needham (1970). Atoms and Molecules. California: Benjamin Cummings. p. 68 ISBN 978-0805352184. OCLC 984466711
  43. ^ The broad linewidth of fast-decaying states makes it difficult to accurately measure the energy of the state, and researchers have even used detuned microwave cavities to slow down the decay rate, to get sharper peaks. Gabrielse, Gerald; H. Dehmelt (1985). "Observation of Inhibited Spontaneous Emission". Physical Review Letters. 55 (1): 67–70. Bibcode:1985PhRvL..55...67G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.55.67. PMID 10031682.
  44. ^ a b Hilgevoord, Jan (March 2005). "Time in quantum mechanics: a story of confusion". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 36 (1): 29–60. Bibcode:2005SHPMP..36...29H. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2004.10.002. Archived from the original on 2022-10-23. Retrieved 2024-01-28.
  45. ^ Bohm, Arno (January 2011). "Resonances/decaying states and the mathematics of quantum physics". Reports on Mathematical Physics. 67 (3): 279–303. Bibcode:2011RpMP...67..279B. doi:10.1016/S0034-4877(11)60018-9. Archived from the original on 2023-12-04. Retrieved 2024-01-24.
  46. ^ Aharonov, Y.; Bohm, D. (June 1, 1961). "Time in the Quantum Theory and the Uncertainty Relation for Time and Energy" (PDF). Physical Review. 122 (5): 1649–1658. Bibcode:1961PhRv..122.1649A. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.122.1649. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-01-09. Retrieved 2012-01-21.
  47. ^ L. I. Mandelstam, I. E. Tamm, The uncertainty relation between energy and time in nonrelativistic quantum mechanics Archived 2019-06-07 at the Wayback Machine, 1945.
  48. ^ Naber, Gregory L. (2021). Quantum Mechanics: An Introduction to the Physical Background and Mathematical Structure. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. p. 230. ISBN 978-3-11-075194-9. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-20.
  49. ^ Havin, V.; Jöricke, B. (1994), The Uncertainty Principle in Harmonic Analysis, Springer-Verlag
  50. ^ Folland, Gerald; Sitaram, Alladi (May 1997), "The Uncertainty Principle: A Mathematical Survey", Journal of Fourier Analysis and Applications, 3 (3): 207–238, doi:10.1007/BF02649110, MR 1448337, S2CID 121355943
  51. ^ Sitaram, A (2001) [1994], "Uncertainty principle, mathematical", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press
  52. ^ Mallat, S. G. (2009). A wavelet tour of signal processing: the sparse way. Amsterdam ; Boston: Elsevier/Academic Press. p. 44. doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-374370-1.X0001-8. ISBN 978-0-12-374370-1.
  53. ^ Donoho, D.L.; Stark, P.B (1989). "Uncertainty principles and signal recovery". SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics. 49 (3): 906–931. doi:10.1137/0149053.
  54. ^ Terence Tao (2005), "An uncertainty principle for cyclic groups of prime order", Mathematical Research Letters, 12 (1): 121–127, arXiv:math/0308286, doi:10.4310/MRL.2005.v12.n1.a11, S2CID 8548232
  55. ^ Amrein, W.O.; Berthier, A.M. (1977), "On support properties of Lp-functions and their Fourier transforms", Journal of Functional Analysis, 24 (3): 258–267, doi:10.1016/0022-1236(77)90056-8.
  56. ^ Benedicks, M. (1985), "On Fourier transforms of functions supported on sets of finite Lebesgue measure", J. Math. Anal. Appl., 106 (1): 180–183, doi:10.1016/0022-247X(85)90140-4
  57. ^ Nazarov, F. (1994), "Local estimates for exponential polynomials and their applications to inequalities of the uncertainty principle type", St. Petersburg Math. J., 5: 663–717
  58. ^ Jaming, Ph. (2007), "Nazarov's uncertainty principles in higher dimension", J. Approx. Theory, 149 (1): 30–41, arXiv:math/0612367, doi:10.1016/j.jat.2007.04.005, S2CID 9794547
  59. ^ Hardy, G.H. (1933), "A theorem concerning Fourier transforms", Journal of the London Mathematical Society, 8 (3): 227–231, doi:10.1112/jlms/s1-8.3.227
  60. ^ Hörmander, L. (1991), "A uniqueness theorem of Beurling for Fourier transform pairs", Ark. Mat., 29 (1–2): 231–240, Bibcode:1991ArM....29..237H, doi:10.1007/BF02384339, S2CID 121375111
  61. ^ Bonami, A.; Demange, B.; Jaming, Ph. (2003), "Hermite functions and uncertainty principles for the Fourier and the windowed Fourier transforms", Rev. Mat. Iberoamericana, 19: 23–55, arXiv:math/0102111, Bibcode:2001math......2111B, doi:10.4171/RMI/337, S2CID 1211391
  62. ^ Hedenmalm, Haakan (2012), "Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in the sense of Beurling", Journal d'Analyse Mathématique, 118 (2): 691–702, arXiv:1203.5222, Bibcode:2012arXiv1203.5222H, doi:10.1007/s11854-012-0048-9, S2CID 54533890
  63. ^ Demange, Bruno (2009), Uncertainty Principles Associated to Non-degenerate Quadratic Forms, Société Mathématique de France, ISBN 978-2-85629-297-6
  64. ^ Giovannetti, V.; Lloyd, S.; Maccone, L. (2011). "Advances in quantum metrology". Nature Photonics. 5 (4): 222. arXiv:1102.2318. Bibcode:2011NaPho...5..222G. doi:10.1038/nphoton.2011.35. S2CID 12591819.; arXiv Archived 2020-08-06 at the Wayback Machine
  65. ^ Luis, Alfredo (2017-03-13). "Breaking the weak Heisenberg limit". Physical Review A. 95 (3): 032113. arXiv:1607.07668. Bibcode:2017PhRvA..95c2113L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.95.032113. ISSN 2469-9926. S2CID 55838380.
  66. ^ a b Ozawa, Masanao (2003), "Universally valid reformulation of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle on noise and disturbance in measurement", Physical Review A, 67 (4): 42105, arXiv:quant-ph/0207121, Bibcode:2003PhRvA..67d2105O, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.67.042105, S2CID 42012188
  67. ^ Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R. F. (2013). "Proof of Heisenberg's Error-Disturbance Relation". Physical Review Letters. 111 (16): 160405. arXiv:1306.1565. Bibcode:2013PhRvL.111p0405B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.111.160405. PMID 24182239. S2CID 24507489.
  68. ^ Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R. F. (2014). "Heisenberg uncertainty for qubit measurements". Physical Review A. 89 (1): 012129. arXiv:1311.0837. Bibcode:2014PhRvA..89a2129B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.89.012129. S2CID 118383022.
  69. ^ a b Rozema, L. A.; Darabi, A.; Mahler, D. H.; Hayat, A.; Soudagar, Y.; Steinberg, A. M. (2012). "Violation of Heisenberg's Measurement–Disturbance Relationship by Weak Measurements". Physical Review Letters. 109 (10): 100404. arXiv:1208.0034v2. Bibcode:2012PhRvL.109j0404R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.109.100404. PMID 23005268. S2CID 37576344.
  70. ^ Erhart, J.; Sponar, S.; Sulyok, G.; Badurek, G.; Ozawa, M.; Hasegawa, Y. (2012). "Experimental demonstration of a universally valid error-disturbance uncertainty relation in spin measurements". Nature Physics. 8 (3): 185–189. arXiv:1201.1833. Bibcode:2012NatPh...8..185E. doi:10.1038/nphys2194. S2CID 117270618.
  71. ^ Baek, S.-Y.; Kaneda, F.; Ozawa, M.; Edamatsu, K. (2013). "Experimental violation and reformulation of the Heisenberg's error-disturbance uncertainty relation". Scientific Reports. 3: 2221. Bibcode:2013NatSR...3E2221B. doi:10.1038/srep02221. PMC 3713528. PMID 23860715.
  72. ^ Ringbauer, M.; Biggerstaff, D.N.; Broome, M.A.; Fedrizzi, A.; Branciard, C.; White, A.G. (2014). "Experimental Joint Quantum Measurements with Minimum Uncertainty". Physical Review Letters. 112 (2): 020401. arXiv:1308.5688. Bibcode:2014PhRvL.112b0401R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.112.020401. PMID 24483993. S2CID 18730255.
  73. ^ Björk, G.; Söderholm, J.; Trifonov, A.; Tsegaye, T.; Karlsson, A. (1999). "Complementarity and the uncertainty relations". Physical Review. A60 (3): 1878. arXiv:quant-ph/9904069. Bibcode:1999PhRvA..60.1874B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.60.1874. S2CID 27371899.
  74. ^ Fujikawa, Kazuo (2012). "Universally valid Heisenberg uncertainty relation". Physical Review A. 85 (6): 062117. arXiv:1205.1360. Bibcode:2012PhRvA..85f2117F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.85.062117. S2CID 119640759.
  75. ^ Judge, D. (1964), "On the uncertainty relation for angle variables", Il Nuovo Cimento, 31 (2): 332–340, Bibcode:1964NCim...31..332J, doi:10.1007/BF02733639, S2CID 120553526
  76. ^ Bouten, M.; Maene, N.; Van Leuven, P. (1965), "On an uncertainty relation for angle variables", Il Nuovo Cimento, 37 (3): 1119–1125, Bibcode:1965NCim...37.1119B, doi:10.1007/BF02773197, S2CID 122838645
  77. ^ Louisell, W. H. (1963), "Amplitude and phase uncertainty relations", Physics Letters, 7 (1): 60–61, Bibcode:1963PhL.....7...60L, doi:10.1016/0031-9163(63)90442-6
  78. ^ DeWitt, B. S.; Graham, N. (1973), The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 52–53, ISBN 0-691-08126-3
  79. ^ Hirschman, I. I. Jr. (1957), "A note on entropy", American Journal of Mathematics, 79 (1): 152–156, doi:10.2307/2372390, JSTOR 2372390.
  80. ^ Beckner, W. (1975), "Inequalities in Fourier analysis", Annals of Mathematics, 102 (6): 159–182, doi:10.2307/1970980, JSTOR 1970980, PMC 432369, PMID 16592223.
  81. ^ Bialynicki-Birula, I.; Mycielski, J. (1975), "Uncertainty Relations for Information Entropy in Wave Mechanics", Communications in Mathematical Physics, 44 (2): 129–132, Bibcode:1975CMaPh..44..129B, doi:10.1007/BF01608825, S2CID 122277352, archived from the original on 2021-02-08, retrieved 2021-08-17
  82. ^ Huang, Yichen (24 May 2011). "Entropic uncertainty relations in multidimensional position and momentum spaces". Physical Review A. 83 (5): 052124. arXiv:1101.2944. Bibcode:2011PhRvA..83e2124H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.83.052124. S2CID 119243096.
  83. ^ Chafaï, D. (2003), "Gaussian maximum of entropy and reversed log-Sobolev inequality", Séminaire de Probabilités XXXVI, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1801, pp. 194–200, arXiv:math/0102227, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-36107-7_5, ISBN 978-3-540-00072-3, S2CID 17795603
  84. ^ Chiew, Shao-Hen; Gessner, Manuel (31 January 2022). "Improving sum uncertainty relations with the quantum Fisher information". Physical Review Research. 4 (1): 013076. arXiv:2109.06900. Bibcode:2022PhRvR...4a3076C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013076. S2CID 237513883.
  85. ^ Whittaker, Edmund T. (1989). A history of the theories of aether & electricity. Vol. II: The modern theories, 1900–1926 (Repr ed.). New York: Dover Publ. p. 267. ISBN 978-0-486-26126-3.
  86. ^ "This Month in Physics History". www.aps.org. Archived from the original on 2011-01-30. Retrieved 2023-11-04.
  87. ^ a b c Heisenberg, W. (1930), Physikalische Prinzipien der Quantentheorie (in German), Leipzig: Hirzel English translation The Physical Principles of Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1930.
  88. ^ Heisenberg, W., Die Physik der Atomkerne, Taylor & Francis, 1952, p. 30.
  89. ^ Cassidy, David; Saperstein, Alvin M. (2009), "Beyond Uncertainty: Heisenberg, Quantum Physics, and the Bomb", Physics Today, 63 (1), New York: Bellevue Literary Press: 185, Bibcode:2010PhT....63a..49C, doi:10.1063/1.3293416, archived from the original on Jan 4, 2024
  90. ^ Greenstein, George; Zajonc, Arthur (2006). The Quantum Challenge: Modern Research on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-0-7637-2470-2.
  91. ^ Tipler, Paul A.; Llewellyn, Ralph A. (1999), Modern Physics, vol. 3, W.H. Freeman & Co., p. 3, ISBN 978-1572591646, LCCN 98046099
  92. ^ Furuta, Aya (2012), "One Thing Is Certain: Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle Is Not Dead", Scientific American, archived from the original on 2022-04-01, retrieved 2018-10-20
  93. ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1978-01-01), Marlow, A. R. (ed.), "The 'Past' and the 'Delayed-Choice' Double-Slit Experiment", Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theory, Academic Press, pp. 9–48, doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-473250-6.50006-6, ISBN 978-0-12-473250-6, archived from the original on 2022-12-10, retrieved 2023-07-19
  94. ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (1977), Lopes, José Leite; Paty, Michel (eds.), "Include the Observer in the Wave Function?", Quantum Mechanics, A Half Century Later: Papers of a Colloquium on Fifty Years of Quantum Mechanics, Held at the University Louis Pasteur, Strasbourg, May 2–4, 1974, Episteme, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 1–18, doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1196-9_1, ISBN 978-94-010-1196-9, archived from the original on 2024-02-23, retrieved 2023-07-19
  95. ^ Werner Heisenberg, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, p. 20
  96. ^ De Broglie, Louis (October 1923). "Waves and Quanta". Nature. 112 (2815): 540. Bibcode:1923Natur.112..540D. doi:10.1038/112540a0. ISSN 1476-4687. S2CID 186242764.
  97. ^ Indian Institute of Technology Madras, Professor V. Balakrishnan, Lecture 1 – Introduction to Quantum Physics; Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, National Programme of Technology Enhanced Learning on YouTube
  98. ^ Enz, Charles Paul; von Meyenn, Karl (1994). Writings on Physics and Philosophy by Wolfgang Pauli. Translated by Robert Schlapp. Springer-Verlag. p. 43. ISBN 3-540-56859-X. Archived from the original on 2020-08-19. Retrieved 2018-02-10.
  99. ^ Feynman lectures on Physics, vol 3, 2–2
  100. ^ a b Gamow, G., The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein, Courier Dover, 1988, p.260.
  101. ^ Kumar, M., Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality, Icon, 2009, p. 282.
  102. ^ Gamow, G., The great physicists from Galileo to Einstein, Courier Dover, 1988, pp. 260–261. [ISBN missing]
  103. ^ Kumar, M., Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the Great Debate About the Nature of Reality, Icon, 2009, p. 287.
  104. ^ Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
  105. ^ Kumar, Manjit (2011). Quantum: Einstein, Bohr and the great debate about the nature of reality (1st pbk. ed.). New York: Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-33988-8.
  106. ^ a b c Popper, Karl (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Hutchinson & Co.
  107. ^ Jarvie, Ian Charles; Milford, Karl; Miller, David W (2006), Karl Popper: a centenary assessment, vol. 3, Ashgate Publishing, ISBN 978-0-7546-5712-5
  108. ^ Popper, Karl; Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker (1934), "Zur Kritik der Ungenauigkeitsrelationen (Critique of the Uncertainty Relations)", Naturwissenschaften, 22 (48): 807–808, Bibcode:1934NW.....22..807P, doi:10.1007/BF01496543, S2CID 40843068.
  109. ^ Popper, K. Quantum theory and the schism in Physics, Unwin Hyman Ltd, 1982, pp. 53–54.
  110. ^ Mehra, Jagdish; Rechenberg, Helmut (2001), The Historical Development of Quantum Theory, Springer, ISBN 978-0-387-95086-0
  111. ^ Compton, A. H. (1931). "The Uncertainty Principle and Free Will". Science. 74 (1911): 172. Bibcode:1931Sci....74..172C. doi:10.1126/science.74.1911.172. PMID 17808216. S2CID 29126625.
  112. ^ Heisenberg, M. (2009). "Is free will an illusion?". Nature. 459 (7244): 164–165. Bibcode:2009Natur.459..164H. doi:10.1038/459164a. PMID 19444190. S2CID 4420023.
  113. ^ a b Davies, P.C.W. (2004). "Does quantum mechanics play a non-trivial role in life?". Biosystems. 78 (1–3): 69–79. Bibcode:2004BiSys..78...69D. doi:10.1016/j.biosystems.2004.07.001. PMID 15555759.
  114. ^ Hänggi, Esther; Wehner, Stephanie (2013). "A violation of the uncertainty principle implies a violation of the second law of thermodynamics". Nature Communications. 4: 1670. arXiv:1205.6894. Bibcode:2013NatCo...4.1670H. doi:10.1038/ncomms2665. PMID 23575674. S2CID 205316392.
  115. ^ Kemble, E. C., 1937, The Fundamental Principles of Quantum Mechanics (McGraw-Hill, New York; reprinted by Dover), p. 244
  116. ^ Haag, R. (1996), Local Quantum Physics: Fields, Particles, Algebras, (Berlin: Springer).[page needed][ISBN missing]
  117. ^ Peres, Asher; Terno, Daniel R. (2004-01-06). "Quantum information and relativity theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 76 (1): 93–123 [111]. arXiv:quant-ph/0212023. Bibcode:2004RvMP...76...93P. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93. ISSN 0034-6861. S2CID 7481797. Archived from the original on 2024-02-23. Retrieved 2024-01-25.
  118. ^ Elion, W. J.; Matters, M.; Geigenmüller, U.; Mooij, J. E. (1994), "Direct demonstration of Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in a superconductor", Nature, 371 (6498): 594–595, Bibcode:1994Natur.371..594E, doi:10.1038/371594a0, S2CID 4240085
  119. ^ Smithey, D. T.; M. Beck, J. Cooper, M. G. Raymer; Cooper, J.; Raymer, M. G. (1993), "Measurement of number–phase uncertainty relations of optical fields", Phys. Rev. A, 48 (4): 3159–3167, Bibcode:1993PhRvA..48.3159S, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.48.3159, PMID 9909968{{citation}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  120. ^ Caves, Carlton (1981), "Quantum-mechanical noise in an interferometer", Phys. Rev. D, 23 (8): 1693–1708, Bibcode:1981PhRvD..23.1693C, doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.23.1693
edit