[go: up one dir, main page]

In Kantian philosophy, a transcendental schema (plural: schemata; from ‹See Tfd›Greek: σχῆμα, 'form, shape, figure') is the procedural rule by which a category or pure, non-empirical concept is associated with a sense impression. A private, subjective intuition is thereby discursively thought to be a representation of an external object. Transcendental schemata are supposedly produced by the imagination in relation to time.

Role in Kant's architectonic system

edit

Kant created an architectonic system in which there is a progression of phases from the most formal to the most empirical:[1] "Kant develops his system of corporeal nature in the following way. He starts in the Critique with the most formal act of human cognition, called by him the transcendental unity of apperception, and its various aspects, called the logical functions of judgment. He then proceeds to the pure categories of the understanding, and then to the schematized categories, and finally to the transcendental principles of nature in general."[2] It is within this system that the transcendental schemata are supposed to serve a crucial purpose. Many interpreters of Kant have emphasized the importance of the schematism.[3][4][5][6][7][8][9][10]

Purpose of the schematism chapter

edit

If pure concepts of the understanding (Kantian Categories) and sense perceptions are radically different from each other, what common quality allows them to relate? Kant wrote the chapter on Schematism in his Critique of Pure Reason to solve the problem of "...how we can ensure that categories have 'sense and significance.' "[11][12]

A posteriori concepts have sense when they are derived from a mental image that is based on experienced sense impressions. Kant's a priori concepts, on the other hand, are alleged to have sense when they are derived from a non–experienced mental schema, trace, outline, sketch, monogram,[13] or minimal image. This is similar to a Euclidean geometrical diagram.

Whenever two things are totally different from each other, yet must interact, there must be some common characteristic that they share in order to somehow relate to one another. Kantian Categories, or a priori concepts, have, according to Kant, a basic and necessary importance for human knowledge, even though they are totally different from sensations. However, they must be connected in some way with sensed experience[14] because "… an a priori concept which cannot, as it were, establish any empirical connections is a fraud … the purpose of the Schematism chapter was to show that the categories at least do have satisfactory empirical connections."[15] Kant was preoccupied "with bridging the otherwise heterogeneous poles of 'thought' and 'sensation' in the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding (A 138/B 177)."[16][17]

Explication of the Kantian account of schemata

edit

Three types of concept and their schemata

edit

There are three types of concept that require a schema in order to connect them to phenomenal sense perceptions so that they have sense [Sinn] and meaning [Bedeutung]. These three types are (1) empirical concepts, (2) pure (mathematical) sensuous concepts, and (3) pure concepts of the understanding, or [Kantian] Categories. The first two employ schemata. The third employs transcendental schemata.

Empirical concepts

edit

An empirical concept[18] is the abstract thought of that which is common to several perceptions. When an empirical concept is said to contain an object, whatever is thought in the concept must be intuited in the mental representation of the object.[19] Examples of intuitive perceptions that are the content of empirical concepts are vague images that are imagined in order to connect a concept with the perceptions from which it was derived as their common feature.[20] "Intuitions," Kant wrote, "are always required to verify or demonstrate the reality of our concepts."[21] These examples ensure that "our abstract thinking has not strayed far from the safe ground of perception, and has possibly become somewhat high-flown or even a mere idle display of words."[22] This is because "concepts are quite impossible, and are utterly without meaning or signification, unless an object is given for the concepts themselves, or at least for the elements of which they consist."[23] For example, "The concept of a dog signifies a rule according to which my imagination can trace, delineate, or draw a general outline, figure, or shape of a four-footed animal without being restricted to any single and particular shape supplied by experience."[24] In order to prevent the emptiness of "thoughts without contents,"[25] it is "necessary to make our concepts sensible, i.e., to add an object of intuition to them."[25] In order to test whether a concept is sensible, we sometimes " … go back to perception only tentatively and for the moment, by calling up in imagination a perception corresponding to the concept that occupies us at the moment, a perception that can never be quite adequate to the (general) concept, but is a mere representative of it for the time being. … Kant calls a fleeting phantasm of this kind a schema."[26]

Pure sensuous (mathematical) concepts

edit

These are concepts that relate, prior to experience, to the external sense of space and the internal sense of time. As such, they are mathematical in that they refer to geometry and arithmetic. A pure, sensuous concept is the construction or mental drawing of what is common to several geometrical figures. These mathematical concepts are not based on objective visual images. They are based on schemata that exist only in thought. Any particular image could not be as general as the concept.[24] The schemata are rules that allow the imagination to mentally construct or draw or trace a pure, general geometrical form that gives the pure, sensuous concept significance. "… [T]o possess the schema corresponding to the concept triangle is to be able to envisage the variety of things to which the word "triangle" applies."[27] "[T]he schema of sensuous concepts (such as of figures in space) is a product and, as it were, a monogram of the pure imagination a priori. Images become possible only through the schema. But the images must always be connected with the concept only by means of the designated schema. Otherwise, the images can never be fully congruent to the general concept."[28]

Pure concepts of the understanding (Categories)

edit

A pure concept of the understanding, or category, is a characteristic, predicate, attribute, quality, or property of any possible object, that is, an object in general or as such. These concepts are not abstractions of what is common to several perceived, particular, individual objects, as are empirical concepts. "Since the categories are a priori and are therefore not abstractions from sense perceptions, they owe their origin to the very nature of the mind itself."[29] They are not derived from perceptions of external objects, as are empirical concepts. Instead, they are the result of the way that the mind is constituted or formed. They come from within the mind, not from outside of the mind.

Kant claimed that the schemata of pure, non-empirical concepts, or categories, provide a reference to intuition in a way similar to the manner of empirical concepts.[30] "If the concepts are empirical, the intuitions are called examples; if they are pure concepts of the understanding, the intuitions are called schemata."[21] In the same way that examples provide signification for empirical concepts, schemata help to answer the question of "whether operating with the categories is anything other than playing with words."[31]

Since the pure concepts of the understanding, or categories, are characteristics of all objects in general, they can never be associated with the image of any specific, particular, individual object. "Since they are pure, they cannot be pictures..."[29] "Yet there must be some connection between the abstract idea and the experienced world to which the idea is expected to apply..."[27] "In order for the pure categories to have objective validity (and not merely subjective validity) they must be related to sensibility."[29][32]

Applying pure concepts to sense impressions
edit

The categories, or pure concepts of the understanding,[33] are a priori logical innate forms that are conditions of the possibility of things in general, or of things as such.[34] A thing can become a known object of thought when an a posteriori sense impression is comprehended through the forms of the categories. Categories and sense impressions are totally different from each other. Categories are utterly heterogeneous with the perceptions that are experienced through the sense organs. In order for specific phenomena of Nature to be thought from the combination of categories (pure concepts) and sense perceptions, there must be a third, mediating procedure that connects them. This mediator is a transcendental schema.[35] Transcendental schemata meaningfully join the empty "thoughts without content" and the blind "intuitions without concepts."[25]

Schemata that mediate between empirical (a posteriori) concepts or mathematical (pure sensuous) concepts and perceptions are similar to adapters. Just as adapters are devices for fitting together incompatible parts, schemata connect empirical concepts with the perceptions from which they were derived. Schemata are rules for the production of images. As rules, they are related to concepts. As image–producers, they are related to perceptions. "While the concept belongs to the understanding and its instance to perception, the schema has, so to speak, a foot in either domain. As rules for the production of images the schemata … are linked to the understanding; as rules for the production of images they are linked to perception."[36] The "adapter" simile is even more apt in the case of transcendental schemata. This is because pure concepts of the understanding (Categories) are totally unrelated to perceptions. The pure concepts or Categories are original constituent components of the understanding and are not derived from empirical sense perceptions.

Transcendental schemata
edit

Transcendental schema are not related to empirical concepts or to mathematical concepts. These schemata connect pure concepts of the understanding, or categories, to the phenomenal appearance of objects in general, that is, objects as such, or all objects.[37]

Judgment
edit

Transcendental Schematism results from the ability to make judgments. Judgment applies "the concepts of the understanding [the Categories] to phenomena."[38] " … [T]he judgment … schematizes these concepts a priori and applies these schemata, without which no experiential judgment would be possible, to each empirical synthesis. … the transcendental schematism of judgment provides it [judgment] with a rule under which given empirical intuitions are to be subsumed."[39] Kant defined the Greek word hypotyposis as a " … rendering perceptible to the senses, making sensual (Versinnlichung)."[21] The usual definition is "example, pattern, outline, or sketch." If a hypotyposis is schematic, according to Kant, "...to a concept, which is comprehended by the understanding, the corresponding intuition is given a priori..."[21] This is in opposition to a symbolic hypotyposis, like God, in which the concept can only be thought by Reason and to which no sensible intuition can be adequate. Schemata contain direct presentations of the concept. They make this presentation demonstratively, not by the use of analogies. Judgment, according to Kant, works mechanically with given appearances and brings them under concepts. It does this as a tool that is utilized and controlled by both the understanding and the senses.[40] To avoid possible mistakes in judgments one must conduct the transcendental reflection.[41]

Time
edit

The schematism of the pure understanding is "the sensuous condition [time] under which alone pure concepts of the understanding [the Categories] can be used."[42] Categories, or pure concepts of the understanding, are abstract representations of objects in general. However, they can result in thought about particular, specific internal or external objects if they are related to time. All concepts are derived from perceptions, therefore pure concepts [Categories] are based on pure perceptions. The purest perception, or schema, is time. Time has the purest relation to sensation that is possible. It is the mere form of sensation because sensations must be felt in succession. Therefore, time was designated by Kant as the purest possible schema of a pure concept.

All things are experienced in time, that is, in succession, one after another. This applies to our internal selves as well as to all external objects. Since categories are the forms through which every specific thing can be thought as being in time, categories are related to time. Thus, pure concepts, or categories, and phenomenal objects share time as a common feature. Therefore, time is the means by which an intuited phenomenon is subsumed under a pure concept. Schemata are transcendental time determinations. "Hence it will be possible for the category to be applied to appearances by means of the transcendental time determination, which, as the schema of the concepts of the understanding, mediates the subsumption of appearances under the category."[34][43]

Schemata are procedural rules, not images
edit

Because schemata are determinations of objects in general, not specific, individual objects, they are not particular images. Kant asserted that "… a schema must be distinguished from an image."[23] A schema is a procedural rule.[44] The rule prescribes the way to relate a pure concept to an object in general. Schemata are ways of applying pure concepts (categories) to sense impressions. They are prescriptions for graphically illustrating a pure concept. A schema is a method for representing a non-empirical concept in any image as such or any image in general. " … [F]or Kant a schema is not an image, but a capacity to form images or (perhaps) to construct models."[27] "The schema of a pure concept of the understanding is something which can never be made into an image..."[28]

Lewis White Beck[45] wrote, "The pure concepts of the understanding…are applied to the pure form of intuition (time) to give rise to the 'transcendental schemata' or rules of the application of pure concepts to whatever sense–impressions we receive." To exemplify this, he continued, "To take the most important example, we have the hypothetical (if–then) judgment, which is the mode of judgment under the category of cause. This is applied to phenomena in time by the schema of causation, namely, the rule that the cause of a phenomenon is another phenomenon that invariably precedes it in time…." In this way, Beck showed that a transcendental schema is the rule that leads to the understanding of successive [in time] sensations according to various pure concepts [Kant's "categories"].

Examples of different categories and their schemata
edit

Each category has one schema. Some schemas are shared by other categories in their class.[46]

  • The categories of quantity all share the schema of number. Quantity is related to a numerical time series. William H.S. Monck claimed that Kant can be understood as saying "In apprehending an object I always successively add part to part, and thus generate a series of determinate magnitude."[47] Unity is one moment in time. Plurality is several moments. Totality is expressed as all moments. But Monck noted that "Kant does not trace out specially the Schemata of the Categories of Unity, Plurality, and Totality."[47] Monck supposed: "In the Category of Unity I presume we should stop at the first term of the Time–series: for the Category of Plurality we should represent the addition of unit to unit without laying down any determinate limit; and for the Category of Totality we should limit the number of units and complete the addition up to this number."[48]
  • The categories of quality all have degrees of reality as their schema. Quality is related to the content of real being in time. Kant metaphorically explained the schema of quality as the filling up of time with a sensation. Monck paraphrased Kant as saying, "We may speak of time as being more completely filled when the sensation is more vivid, and less completely filled when the sensation is weaker. If the sensation is sufficiently vivid the present moment is so filled with it that it seems impossible to attend to, or even be conscious of any other sensation simultaneously; but when it becomes weaker we have leisure to perceive other sensations also.[49] This occurs by degrees. "We can represent this filling as taking place by a gradual increase from zero (empty time) to any given degree of vividness, or by a similar descent from the sensation of the moment to zero."[49] Reality is the experience of sensation in time. Negation is the absence of sensation in time. Limitation is the range of degrees, between the transition from full to empty, by which things are sensed in time. But Monck stated that "Again Kant does not here give in detail the Schemata of the Categories of Reality, Negation, and Limitation." He qualifiedly suggested that "In the first case [Reality], we should, perhaps, represent the sensation as occupying the present moment to the exclusion of everything else; in the second [Negation] the sensation as entirely absent from the present moment; in the third [Limitation] the sensation as occupying the present moment along with others.[49]
  • "The Schema of the Category of Relation is the Order of Time."[50] In the class of relation, each category has its own schema. Substance's schema is the permanence of the unchanging substance (subject) to which accidents (predicates) belong, or the permanence of the object in time. Causality's schema is the necessary succession of a consequent to an antecedent. That is, "… the Schema of the Category of Cause is its regular Antecedence in Time (i.e. Succession in Time determined by fixed law)."[51] The category of community has the schema of the necessary coexistence of the accidents of one substance with the accidents of another substance. This communal interaction consists of the changing accidents of one substance having their cause in the changing accidents of another substance, and vice versa.[29] This can be understood as "… the Simultaneity of objects in Time."[51]
  • "The Schema of the Category of Modality according to Kant is Time itself as related to the Existence of the object."[49] In the class of modality, the category of possibility has the schema of possibility at any time. The schema of actual existence at a certain time belongs to the category of existence. Finally, the category of necessity has the schema of being an object at all times.[52]

Even though Kant provided these illustrations and examples of schemata, author John Mahaffy claimed that the topic remained obscure. He wrote, "I may add, that these illustrations of the various schemata are developed and explained by the succeeding chapters on the Principles which embody them, and that it is impossible to make them clear to the reader until he has studied the theory of the Principles."[53]

Schematized and unschematized categories
edit

The schemata give the categories a "cash value",[54] as though the category is like paper money and sense experience is analogous to precious metal. A schema is the agreement or harmony of a category with sensual phenomena. For example, "Number is the quantity of the phenomenon; sensation is the reality of the phenomenon; the permanence and endurance of things is the substance of the phenomenon, eternity is the necessity of the phenomenon, etc."[55] In this way, the schemata restrict the categories to conditions of sensibility. "Schematism and the schemas thus have the property of 'realizing' the categories at the same time as restricting their scope to appearances."[56] Categories cannot be realized in objects that are not detectable by the senses, that is, are not phenomenal objects (objects that appear to an observer).

"The schemata of the pure concepts of the understanding are, therefore, the true and sole conditions for providing these concepts with a reference to objects and hence with signification. And therefore the categories have, in the end, no other use than a possible empirical one."[55] In order for categories to refer to perceived, experienced objects, they must be schematized. If a category is not schematized, then it has no reference to perception. An unschematized category can be thought, but can not be known. If something can never be perceived, it can never be known. Schemata represent things in general as they appear, not as they might otherwise exist. "Categories, therefore, without schemata are only functions of the understanding necessary for concepts, but do not themselves represent any object."[57] This act results in the formation of one abstract concept from various perceptions or other concepts. With the transcendental determination of time as the transcendental schema, " … use of the categories is clearly restricted to the range of things that fall within time — meaning, for Kant, restricted to phenomena."[27] Metaphysical entities that are not related to time, such as spontaneous or uncaused movements, immortal souls, and eternal gods, are products of unschematized categories. They can be thought, but not known.

Unschematized concepts
edit

Two kinds of concepts do not use schemata in order to exhibit their empirical bases: rational concepts (ideas of reason), and Platonic Ideas. With these concepts or ideas, there is no intermediate nexus between abstract entity and concrete sense perception. These unschematized concepts do not contain or subsume a representation of an object that is the basis of a concept.

Kant listed three rational concepts or ideas of reason: God, freedom, and immortality. They are not found in experience.[58] “…[T]he difficulty about ideas of reason is that ‘absolutely no intuition commensurate with these can be given’ (Critique of Judgment, § 59).” [59] “To make sense of such ideas we must accordingly have recourse to an alternative procedure, in which use is made of ‘symbols’ as opposed to schemata proper. What happens here is…that we find some empirically intuitable situation which can serve as a model by reference to which the idea can be made comprehensible.”[59] For example, Kant tried to show how sense can be made of the idea of an unseen God “by making a [loving or angry] father’s relationship to his children the [metaphorical, figurative] symbol of God’s relationship to the world.”[60] The rational idea of a non-deterministic occurrence can be spoken of in reference to the analogies of the universe as a mechanism [such as a clock] or organism. Thus, while pure concepts of understanding, empirical, and pure sensible concepts are directly exhibited and made sensible through schemata, ideas of reason are indirectly exhibited through relations by the use of symbolic analogy.[60]

Professor W. H. Walsh attempted to explain how schemata are used to make sense of, or exhibit, the twelve Kantian categories (pure concepts of the understanding) while symbolic analogous relationships are used for the three rational concepts (ideas of reason). "It may be useful in this connection to compare what Kant says about the schematization, or quasi-schematization, of ideas of reason with what he says about the schematization of categories. The problem in the two cases is in essentials identical: how to make a concrete use of concepts which are by nature remote from sense. To show that such a use is possible we need, in Kant’s technical terminology, to find intuitions corresponding to them. In the case of pure concepts of the understanding this can be done, since we can point to the appropriate schemata; the difficulty about ideas of reason is just that 'absolutely no intuition commensurate with them can be given' (Critique of Judgment, §59). To make sense of such ideas [of reason] we must accordingly have recourse to an alternative procedure, in which use is made of ‘symbols’ as opposed to schemata proper. What happens here is, roughly, that we find some empirically intuitable situation which can serve as a model by reference to which the idea [of reason] can be made comprehensible. The idea of God, for example, is incapable of being schematized, but we can nevertheless make partial sense of it for certain purposes by making a father’s relationship to his children the symbol of God’s relationship to the world....What is noteworthy in this discussion…is…the sharp contrast drawn between schema and symbol, and hence between the meaningfulness of categories and that of ideas [of reason]….every concept capable of schematization…seems to allow that the relationship between idea [of reason] and symbol is altogether less intimate: symbolizing is a relatively arbitrary process, and hence each idea [of reason] can be symbolized in a variety of ways.[61]" A category has one transcendental schema; an idea of reason can have multiple symbols for its analogy.

Plato’s Ideas (also known as notions, forms, paradigms, or archetypes) are concepts that function as patterns or models. They are related to objects in the experienced world[62] Ideas are related to natural objects or their perceptual representations by the processes of participating,[63] partaking,[64] and copying.[65] “The particular objects which we perceive are imperfect copies or reflections of the eternal patterns.”[66]

edit

In von Hartmann’s Philosophy of the Unconscious[67] he declared that Kantian Transcendental Schemata connect unconscious Categories to conscious knowledge. Kant’s Pure Concepts of the Understanding, or Categories, are unconscious representations or ideas[68] that lie beyond knowledge.[69] According to von Hartmann, these unconscious Categories produce conscious knowledge through the mediation[70] of the Schemata of the Pure Understanding.

Alternative schemata

edit

Kant said that the schema of a concept is the representation of a general procedure of the imagination by which an image can be supplied for a concept.[23] Kant claimed that time is the only proper and appropriate transcendental schema because it shares the a priori category's generality and purity as well as any a posteriori phenomenon's manner of appearance. However, it may be true that time is not the only possible schema.

Space

edit

"Even more remarkable, however, is the fact that in order to understand the possibility of things as consequent upon the categories, and hence in order to establish the categories' objective reality, we need not merely intuitions but indeed always outer intuitions."[71] Since space is the form of all appearances of the outer senses, it may seem that space could serve as a schema. Indeed, any phenomenon that requires space, as well as time, as a form would also need a spatial schema." This suggests that he may have thought at one point of recasting the Schematism argument in a fundamental way, by substituting space for time; but if he had this idea, he did not carry it out."[72] In the editor's introduction to his translation of the Critique,[73] Paul Guyer asserted that "…although the content of the transcendental schemata for the categories may be explicated in purely temporal terms, the use of these schemata in turn depends upon judgments about the spatial properties and relations of at least some objects of empirical judgment." Guyer claimed that this declaration was clarified in Kant's "The System of All Principles" section.[74] In this way, the use of schemata is supposed to involve both space and time, instead of merely time.

Norman Kemp Smith claimed that there is apparently no good reason why Kant did not consider space to also be a transcendental schema for his Categories.[75] Kemp Smith argued that consciousness of space is as fundamental as that of time.[76] He concluded that "…Kant’s concentration on the temporal aspect of experience is exceedingly arbitrary…."[77] and therefore without reason. Experience, Kant had claimed, is always spatio-temporal. Inner sense, however, may be exclusively temporal. Kemp Smith then guessed, in opposition to his earlier statement, why Kant ignored space as a transcendental schema. "Possibly Kant’s very natural preoccupation with his new revolutionary doctrine of inner sense and productive imagination has something to do with the matter [i.e., is the reason for his elimination of space]."[77] Thus, Kant's doctrine of inner sense and its emphasis on time resulted in his exclusion of space as a transcendental schema.

A. C. Ewing claimed that the reason that Kant did not use space as a transcendental schema was because space is not needed in order to understand the relational concepts of substance or causality.[78] According to Professor Ewing, Kant did intend to use space as a transcendental schematic mediator between a category and a sensible intuition.[79] Kant, according to Professor Ewing, for one category did use space as a transcendental schema to unify a pure concept with a sensible intuition.[80] Even though space is not needed in order to understand the relations of substance and causality, it is required in order to understand the conceptual relation of community or reciprocity.[81]

Werner Pluhar explained why time, rather than space, is used as a connection to include (subsume) sensory intuition in the Kantian categories or pure concepts of the understanding. “…[A]ll [transcendental] schemata connect the categories with time; the reason for this is that time is the only form of intuition that applies to any intuition whatsoever, even to the inner intuition we have of ourselves, whereas space applies merely to all outer intuitions.” (Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, translated by Werner S. Pluhar, Translator’s Introduction, p. xxxvi, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1987)

Organism

edit

In order to show how time may not be the only schema, Professor Walsh suggested that there is "… the possibility of making sense of the categories in organic as opposed to mechanical terms."[54] He hypothesized that "Elements in an organic complex would here take the place of elements in a temporal situation. Substance might be interpreted in terms of growth and form as opposed to what underlies mechanical change, and causality be thought of in terms of purpose and function."[54] However, Professor Walsh concluded that Kant's choice of time as schema was more precise than any alternative choices. In spite of the general difficulty in understanding Schematism, he asserted that "… Kant's doctrine of schematism, if not altogether satisfactory at the theoretical level, will continue to stand on the strong empirical ground that the schemata offered do enable us to give real meaning to the categories and find for them a genuine use."[54]

Schemata of systematic unity

edit

In his discussion of the Architectonic of Pure Reason,[82] Kant utilized the concept of schema in a way that was similar to his discussion of the schemata of the Categories. A science's whole systematic organization consists of parts. The parts are various cognitions or units of knowledge. The parts are united under one idea which determines the relation of the parts to each other and also the purpose of the whole system. A schema is needed to execute, carry out, or realize this unifying idea and put it into effect. This schema is a sketch or outline of the way that the parts of knowledge are organized into a whole system of science. A schema which is sketched, designed, or drafted in accordance with accidental, empirical purposes results in mere technical unity. But a schema that is drawn up from an a priori rational idea is the foundational outline of architectonic unity. Science must have architectonic unity. "For the schema of what we call science must contain the whole's outline (monogramma) and the whole's division into parts in conformity with the idea — i.e., it must contain these a priori — and must distinguish this whole from all others with certainty and according to principles."[83] This use of the concept of schema is similar to Kant's previous use. It is a minimal outline, monogram, or diagram that realizes or executes an abstract, general concept or idea (Idee) as actual, perceptual experience.

Criticism

edit

Obscurity of the concept "schema"

Kant introduced the concept of the transcendental schema in his chapter entitled "Of the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding."[19] It is considered to be one of Kant's more difficult chapters. Even though he knew that he was not writing for a popular readership, Kant twice tried to apologize for this chapter by calling it "very dry"[84] and "dry and tedious."[28] Kant entered into his 1797 notebook: "In general, the schematism is one of the most difficult points. – Even Herr Beck cannot find his way about in it."[85] Professor W.H. Walsh, of the University of Edinburgh, wrote: "The chapter on Schematism probably presents more difficulties to the uncommitted but sympathetic reader than any other part of the Critique of Pure Reason. Not only are the details of the argument highly obscure (that, after all, is a common enough experience in reading Kant, though one is not often so baffled as one is here): it is hard to say in plain terms what general point or points Kant is seeking to establish."[86] Arthur Schopenhauer referred to it as "…the strange 'Chapter on the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding,' which is well known for its great obscurity, since no one has ever been able to make anything out of it."[87] Schopenhauer's notebooks contained entries that described Kant's chapter on schemata as "an audacious piece of nonsense"[88] and the schema as "an absurdity whose non–existence is plain."[89] Schopenhauer also remarked on "...the futility of such intermediate things between intuitive perception and concepts."[90] In Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata, he attempted to clear up the obscurity by attributing Kant's concept of schemata simply to a psychological need for architectonic symmetry in his writings.[91] Empirical concepts are based on empirical perceptions. Kant, however, tried to claim that, analogously, pure concepts (Categories) also have a basis. But this contradicts his previous assertion that pure concepts simply exist in the human mind and are not based on pure, schematic perceptions. Schopenhauer also alleged that schemata were introduced merely to give plausibility to Kant's description of the categories or pure concepts of the understanding. The article on Kant in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy calls Kant's schematism a "baffling doctrine " with "cryptic sentences."[27] Josiah Royce referred to "the perplexing doctrine of the Schema."[92] The Scottish philosopher Robert Adamson wrote: "Kant's manner of explaining the functions of schematism is extremely apt to be misunderstood, and to mislead."[93] Kant's early critics (1782 –1789) did not discuss schematism because they couldn't follow Kant's explanation.[94] Heidegger wrote of "the dryness and tediousness of this analysis…."[95] After more than two centuries, Kant's explanation of schema still seems to be unclear to many readers. In their book on parallel distributed processing, the PDP Research Group discussed Kant's schemata when they appropriated that word to designate their concept of image schemata. "The schema," they wrote, "throughout history, has been a concept shrouded in mystery. Kant's … use of the term has been provocative but difficult to understand."[96] After this sentence, no further attempt was made to discuss Kant's term and the concept that it designates. H. H. Price, in Thinking and Experience, page 292, referred to Kant's Schema and wrote, "…I must confess I do not fully understand it." In 2004, Professor Georges Dicker of SUNY Brockport stated: "I find the Schematism especially opaque…."[97] Kant scholar Norman Kemp Smith judged [98] the schematism chapter to be a "highly artificial argument." Kant's explanation seems, to Kemp Smith, to be contrived and to have no natural progression. Hermann Weyl described his reaction to Kant: "While I had no trouble making this part of Kant’s teaching [regarding a priori space and a priori synthetic judgments] my own, I still had much trouble with the Schematism of Pure Mental Concepts…."[99] In his English lectures, published in 1796, Kant's pupil Friedrich August Nitsch warned his listeners and readers against the difficulty in comprehending Kant's concept of the schema. He wrote: "It will require great efforts of abstraction in the reader to conceive the Schematism of the intellect, in a perfectly clear manner.[100] In his essay "Kant’s Conception of the Categories," T. K. Seung called "…the 'Schematism,' perhaps the most oracular[101] chapter of the Critique….".[102] Professor Eva Schaper wrote that “Schematism…has posed problems for interpreters, and many have wondered whether Kant’s thought had fully matured at the time he wrote it.”[103]

According to Kant, a transcendental schema is a mediating nexus, a third thing (tertium quid; ein Drittes),[104] between a pure concept and a phenomenon.[105] This mediation was never satisfactorily explained by Kant, and Charles Sanders Peirce declared that it is a major part of Kant's system. Kant's "doctrine of the schemata can only have been an afterthought…," Peirce wrote.[106] The theory of mediating schemata was "an addition to his system after it was substantially complete."[107] The enormous importance of the concept of the transcendental schema was emphasized by Peirce when he wrote that "if the schemata had been considered early enough, they would have overgrown his whole work."[107]

Discrepancies

According to Professor W. H. Walsh, there is an apparent discrepancy in Kant's central arguments about schematism. Kant, according to Professor Walsh, first claimed that empirical concepts do not require schemata. Only pure concepts need schemata in order to be realized.[108] This is because pure concepts are totally different from intuitions, whereas, empirical concepts are abstracted from intuitions and are therefore homogeneous with them. But in another part of his chapter, Kant states that mathematical concepts have schemata. "In fact," he wrote, "it is schemata, not images of objects, that lie at the basis of our pure sensible (i.e., geometrical) concepts."[24] In discussing schematism as the method of representing in one image a certain mathematical quantity according to a certain concept, he wrote: "This representation of a general procedure of the imagination by which a concept receives its image, I call the schema of such concept."[23] With regard to pure concepts, Kant then declares, "The schema of a pure concept of the understanding, on the contrary, is something which can never be made into an image … ."[28]

Kant, according to Professor Walsh, has two distinct ways of describing schemata. "Sometimes, as at the beginning of his discussion, he speaks as if a schema were a feature of things which could be pointed to … ".[108] In another place, Kant " … speaks as if schematism were a procedure … ."[108]

Reconciling Irreconcilables

edit

Problematic mediation

The perennial mind-body problem examines the relation between cognitions that are inside of a knower’s brain and objects that appear to be outside of that brain. This dualism is reflected in many philosophical dichotomies.[109] These dichotomies consist of two opposing parts that are totally heterogeneous to each other. Kant was concerned with the problem of uniting these opposites for much of his middle and later life.[110] Descartes incorrectly claimed that the dichotomy of soul and body is unified when the brain’s pineal gland is psychokinetically moved by the brain’s thoughts. Salomon Maimon likened Kant’s Transcendental Schemata to Descartes’ pineal gland.[111] Kant’s concept of Transcendental Schema is understood as being a variation of the enduring mind-body problem because his Transcendental Schema subsumes a sensuous intuition under a pure concept, combining conceptual understanding [mind] with perceptual sensation [body].[112]

Kant’s Three Mediators

In each of his three critiques, Kant described the inclusion of a particular, sensible, concrete intuition in a universal, super-sensible, abstract concept. This inclusion or subsumption occurs, according to Kant, by means of a mediator.

"In the first Critique, Kant introduces the [transcendental] schema by arguing that it is needed to mediate between the pure concepts of the understanding and imagination (intuition). In the second Critique[113] Kant similarly introduces the typus as needed to mediate between reason’s moral law and understanding….In the Critique of Judgment,… Kant justifies his treatment of judgment as…a cognitive power in its own right partly by showing how it mediates between the other two higher cognitive powers, understanding and reason…."

[114]

The three mediators (transcendental schema, typus, and judgment) have nearly equivalent functions. Kant presented the typus mediator (in the second critique) and judgment (as mediator in the third critique) as having nearly the same properties as the transcendental schema mediator (in the first critique).

"The model of the mediating item developed in the Schematism has five features….The mediator must be 1) a third thing, 2) homogeneous with both [heterogeneous] parties, but 3) independent of both as well. It must also be 4) analogical, but, in the case of non-schematic mediation, 5) it must remain at the level of analogy--it must not mediate substantively or materially between the two parties, unlike schematic mediation…."

[115]

Schopenhauer criticized Kant’s use of the first Critique’s organization in Kant’s construction of the second and third Critiques.[116]"The [first critique’s] table of categories is now supposed to be the guiding line along which every metaphysical, and in fact every scientific, speculation is to be conducted (Prolegomena, § 39). In fact, it is not only the foundation of the whole Kantian philosophy, and the type according to which its symmetry is carried through everywhere…but it has also really become the Procrustean bed on to which Kant forces every possible consideration…."

The second Critique’s typus matches the first Critique’s transcendental schema in obscurity.[117] "[E]ven a reader as acute and sophisticated as Jacob Sigismund Beck wrote to Kant in [3 July] 1792 to express his puzzlement over the Typic."[118]

Judgment as Mediator

Judgment, according to Professor Pluhar,[119] mediates between understanding and reason in the following way: "…in a syllogism the power of judgment subsumes the particular under some universal (i.e., under some principle) supplied by understanding and thereby enables reason to make an inference from that universal to the particular." Kant hypothesized that judgment is "…the ability [capacity] to subsume the particular under the universal…."[120] In this way, the two discrete, heterogeneous cognitions, viz., abstract universal and concrete particular, are linked together by means of the mediating judgment. Kant called this mediate linkage "subsumption" [Subsumtion], a verb that denotes the inclusion of a part into a whole.

A Third Thing (ein Drittes)

Kant taught that a Transcendental Schema is a third thing that exists between a perceived phenomenon or appearance and a conceived Category (pure concept of the Understanding).[121] Through the mediation of time, as a third, shared thing, a pure Category that is merely thought can be applied to a phenomenon that is experienced as a sense perception, or, in other words, a phenomenon can be subsumed under a Category.

Previous philosophers had analyzed similar applications or subsumptions while they were investigating heterogeneous relations. They had claimed that an attempt to relate disparate things results in infinite degrees of relation. For example, Plato wrote about an endless series or infinite regress of Forms (i.e., Ideals, Ideas, Paradigms); Aristotle deliberated upon the Third Man Argument.

In Plato’s "Parmenides" dialogue he had Socrates discuss the relationship between a Form and a thing that has a share in the Form. In order for them to relate to each other they must be like each other in some way; they must share some common property. But, in order to relate to the common property, they must share a further common property, and so on to infinity[122]

Aristotle commented on the relation between Plato’s Universal Form of Man and the phenomenal appearance of an individual physical man.[123]

Aristotle’s claim is that, if [the Platonic Form of] Man Itself is separated from the individual men, then, since the individuals and [the Platonic Form] of Man Itself are both men, a "third" man will be predicable (and thus separate from them) of both -- a "fourth" of those three, a "fifth" of the resulting four, and so on.

[124]

The problem of the infinite regress of mediated relations is by-passed if Kant’s use of the "third thing" analogy is understood as being inappropriate. According to Norman Kemp Smith, the Transcendental Schema is not a third thing between a sensed appearance and a thought Category. "[The] relation holding between categories and the material of sense is that of form and matter…," not "…between a class concept and the particulars which can be subsumed under it."[125] "…[T]he true Critical teaching is that category and intuition, that is to say, form and content[126][127] mutually condition one another, and that the so-called schema is simply a name for the latter [intuition or content] as apprehended in terms of the former [category or form].[128]

Adamson's interpretation

edit

Scottish philosopher Robert Adamson wrote from a Hegelian standpoint. He believed that Kant's analysis of knowledge into the separate topics of intuition, schema, and concept was mechanical and artificial. Adamson claimed that "Thought and Intuition are organically united in the schema."[93] "We are not to suppose that the subsumption [of the intuition under the pure notion] is mechanical; that the particular is something distinct from the universal. The union is organic; the particular is only the universal under a special form. The same function of synthesis, which in pure abstraction we call category, is, in realization, the schema, and the intuition is not apart from the schema."[129] Kant's abstract analysis of perceptual knowledge was, according to Adamson, the misleading separation of an organic unity into individual components. He asserted that "… we must on no account regard Notion, Schema, and Intuition, as three parts of perception which would exist in isolation."[130] This amalgamation is typical of the Hegelian "dialectical" formula in which two apparent opposites are always subsumed or reconciled by some third entity.

Pluhar's interpretation

edit

In the translator's introduction to his version of Kant's Critique of Judgment,[131] Werner Pluhar tried to explain schemata. He noted that perceptual intuitions and Kant's conceptual categories are very different, yet they relate to each other. This exposition by Professor Pluhar paraphrases Kant's doctrine that perceptions are based on concepts. Kant's position can be contrasted with Schopenhauer's opposite teaching that concepts are derived or abstracted from perceptions, thereby giving content to the concepts and allowing them to make sense. This is the very reason why pure concepts, or categories, require schemata. "Something is needed," Pluhar wrote, sharing Kant's viewpoint, "to mediate between intuition in general and the categories, viz., a rule or 'schema' that stipulates what conditions the intuition must meet so that it can match a category." Professor Pluhar then gave a specific example of how time is utilized to accomplish the matching or mediation. His explanation does not resort to presenting schemata through the use of visual analogies such as "sketches" or "outlines." Pluhar's schemata are rules. "In the case of causal relation, the schema is the rule that the effect must follow the cause in time." After providing this particular instance, he declared generally that "…all schemata connect the categories with time…." Professor Pluhar then asserted the reason for this schematic connection: "…time is the only form of intuition that applies to any intuition whatsoever, even to the inner intuition that we have of ourselves, whereas space applies merely to all outer intuitions." Oddly enough, schemata do not have to be added as mediators to the categories of causality and substance. These are already temporalized. Time is intrinsic to the relation between cause and effect. Substance, by its very nature, is a thing that continually endures.

Watson on time and schematism

edit

Canadian professor John Watson, in his discussion of Kantian philosophy, wrote about supposed supersensible, atemporal beings such as God or the soul. Such things are said to have a timeless existence. As such, though, they cannot be known or experienced. Watson asserted that "…whatever cannot be ‘schematized’...cannot be known...." [132] He considered Kantian schematization as "...conforming to the process by which the definite or concrete becomes a possible object in time...."[132] Schematizing an object is representing an object in time.[133] Accordingly, timeless "...supersensible realities...are not capable of being 'schematized,' do not admit of the application to them of the [Kantian] categories and can never become objects of actual sensible experience."[132] "In the Critique of Pure Reason it has been maintained that no knowledge of supersensible realities can be obtained, since such knowledge always implies a process of determining [or schematizing] objects in time, whilst the supersensible is necessarily free from the limits of time.[134]" If supersensible objects cannot be schematized because they are not in time, then "…to the supersensible world…the schematized categories have no application….".[135] If a supersensible thing, like God or the soul, is not in time, then it can't be schematized, can't be applied to Kantian categories, and therefore can't be a known object. Such supersensible entities would have to be schematized through the form of time if they were to be known as having sequentially countable magnitude, gradations of intensive reality, permanent substantiality, or successive causality.[136]

Elaborations of Kant's notion of schema in cognitive science

edit

The philosopher Mark Johnson discusses Kant's conception of a schema with respect to developing a theory of the imagination within cognitive science.[137] Johnson's theory makes use of Kant's insights that analogy is the cognitive mechanism which links sensible percepts to their conceptual categories, and that creative analogy—or what Johnson calls conceptual metaphor—is the cognitive mechanism by which we come to have our understanding of those abstract concepts and categories of which we have less direct sensible experience. He proposes that we use imaginative schemata to structure abstract concepts largely in terms a set of spatial analogies he calls image schemata. In Johnson's view, we acquire image schemata primarily from recurrent patterns of experiences in infancy and early childhood, and then reuse these image schemata in a metaphoric fashion both to reason abstractly and as we speak our language.

In an increase of ambiguity and confusion, some cognitive scientists today have appropriated the often–misused technical term "schema" to mean Kantian Category. In his book Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy: Basic Principles and Applications[138] (Jason Aronson Publishers,1996), Robert L. Leahy of the American Institute for Cognitive Therapy in New York City and the Weill Cornell Medical College of Cornell University exemplifies this misuse. In Chapter 2, "Historical Context of Cognitive Therapy," he wrote of how, for Kant, "reality is never directly knowable, but rather is 'known' through 'categories of thinking.'" Leahy then stated, "According to Kant, all knowledge was based on the 'categories' (which today we would call schemas). Consequently, reality was never directly knowable--we only knew the schemas." In this way, Kant's concept of "category," or "pure concept of the understanding," is no longer defined as being a predicate, property, quality, or characteristic of any and all objects in general. A Kantian Category is now vaguely considered by cognitive scientists to be a "schema," which was a term that Kant had already used to designate the subsumption of an empirical intuition, through time, under a category or pure concept.

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ For an explanation of the logical structure of this progression, see Stephen Palmquist, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", Metaphilosophy 17:4 (October 1986), pp. 266–288; revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives: An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993). Also see the third appendix, entitled "Common Objections to Architectonic Reasoning.
  2. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature", Philosophy of Material Nature
  3. ^ "…if the schemata had been considered early enough, they would have overgrown his [Kant’s] whole work." (Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. I, Book I, Chapter I, Section 4, Paragraph 35)
  4. ^ "…if we were to reconsider the problem of Kantian schematism, much of the semantics of this century, from the truth–functional to the structural variety, would find itself in difficulty. And this is what has happened in the area usually referred to as 'cognitive studies.'" (Umberto Eco, Kant and the Platypus, § 3.1)
  5. ^ "The problem of the Schematism of the pure concepts of the understanding is the question concerning the innermost essence of ontological knowledge….The Doctrine of the Schematism of the pure concepts of the understanding is the decisive stage of the laying of the ground for Metaphysica Generalis." (Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics [111], Part 2, § 23)
  6. ^ "The Schematism chapter is not 'confusing,' but rather leads with an unheard-of certainty into the core of the whole problematic of the Critique of Pure Reason." (Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics [112], Part 2, § 23)
  7. ^ "…in his insistence upon the central role of time in consciousness, upon its being in fact the basic character of that synthesis of the finite and the infinite which is the self, Schelling rescues Kant’s schematism from its obscure hiding place in the text of the First Critique and gives it its proper prominence." (Professor Michael Vater of Marquette University in his introduction to Schelling’s System of Transcendental Idealism, p. xvi, 1997, University of Virginia Press)
  8. ^ "…a study of what may be the most puzzling and yet, at the same time, most significant aspect of Kant’s system: his theory of schemata." (Joseph L. Hunter, "Kant’s Doctrine of Schemata," Thesis submitted to the faculty of Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy, August 25, 1999)
  9. ^ "The opaqueness and obscurity of the Schematism chapter—the chapter which Kant himself thought to be one of the most important pieces of the Critique, and to which Hegel paid tribute as being among the finest pages of the entire Kantian oeuvre—has often been—stressed with undertones ranging from wonder to irritation. From among the earliest statements we recall F. H. Jacobi’s assessment of schematism as 'the most wonderful and most mysterious of all unfathomable mysteries and wonders'…." (Shaper, E. (1964–65). "Kant’s Schematism Reconsidered," Review of Metaphysics 18: 270)
  10. ^ John Mahaffy, editor and translator, A Commentary [by Kuno Fischer] on Kant’s Critick of Pure Reason, Introduction, § 3, London, Longmans, Green, & Co., 1866.
  11. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant-Studien, Band 49
  12. ^ "The formation of the schema [Schemabildung] is the making sensible of concepts." (Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, 1997)
  13. ^ A schema is related to a perceived object as a single letter is related to a whole name.
  14. ^ A priori concepts, or Categories, "require, in order to be meaningful and significant, a certain concrete use — that is, an application to some intuition by which an object of them is given to us." Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, § 8.
  15. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant-Studien, vol. 49
  16. ^ The Cambridge Companion to Kant, George di Giovanni, Chapter 14, "The first twenty years of critique: The Spinoza connection," Page 442, Note 6.
  17. ^ Between any two disparate but related things, such as a pure concept and a phenomenal, sensual perception, there must be something that unites, relates, and connects the two. The connector must share some properties with each of those two things that it connects. Kant’s "transcendental schema" is a "third thing, which must stand in homogeneity with the category [pure concept] on the one hand and the phenomenal appearance on the other…." This third, connecting thing must be time, because "a transcendental time-determination is homogeneous with the category (which constitutes its unity) insofar as it is universal and rests on a rule a priori," "but it is on the other hand homogeneous with the phenomenal appearance insofar as time is contained in every empirical representation of the manifold." (Critique of Pure Reason, A 138–9/B 177–8).
  18. ^ "Now if a concept is one drawn from the sensory representation, i.e., an empirical concept, it contains as a characteristic, i.e., as a part-representation, something that was already apprehended in the sensory intuition, and differs from the latter in logical form only, viz., in respect of its generality, e.g., the concept of a four-footed animal in the representation of a horse." (Bold characters added) (Kant, What real progress has metaphysics made in Germany since the time of Leibniz and Wolff?, "First Section Of the Scope of the Theoretico-Dogmatic Use of Pure Reason")
  19. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 137
  20. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Critique of the Kantian Philosophy," p. 449 f.
  21. ^ a b c d Critique of Judgment, § 59
  22. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Critique of the Kantian Philosophy", p. 449
  23. ^ a b c d Critique of Pure Reason, A 140
  24. ^ a b c Critique of Pure Reason, A 141
  25. ^ a b c Critique of Pure Reason, A 51
  26. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I., Appendix, Critique of the Kantian Philosophy. p. 449
  27. ^ a b c d e The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  28. ^ a b c d Critique of Pure Reason, A 142
  29. ^ a b c d Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Part 3
  30. ^ If a Category [Pure Concept] is to generate knowledge, it must be related to a pure intuition or a priori schema. "[I]f the concept is a category, a pure concept of the understanding, it lies entirely outside all intuition, and yet an intuition must be subsumed under it if it is to be used for knowledge; and if this knowledge is to be an a priori cognition, a pure intuition must be underlaid, and one which conforms to the synthetic unity of apperception of the manifold in the intuition which is being thought through the category; i.e., the power of representation must interpose beneath the pure concept of the understanding an a priori schema, without which it could have no object at all, and thus serve for no cognition." (Kant, What real progress has metaphysics made in Germany since the time of Leibniz and Wolff?, "First Section Of the Scope of the Theoretico-Dogmatic Use of Pure Reason")
  31. ^ Walsh, W. H., "Schematism", Kant-Studien, Band 49 (1957)
  32. ^ In a footnote to Kant’s Critique of Judgment ( Indianapolis:Hackett, 1987, p. 110), translator Werner Pluhar noted how a transcendental schema relates a sensible intuition to a pure concept (category) of the understanding: “A schema is what mediates, and so makes possible, the subsumption of intuitions under concepts of the understanding (and so the application of these concepts to intuitions). It does so by sharing features of both a concept and an intuition”.
  33. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A81
  34. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 139
  35. ^ Körner, S., Kant, p. 71ff.
  36. ^ Körner, S., Kant, Chapter 4, p. 70 f.
  37. ^ Körner, S., Kant, p. 72
  38. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 132
  39. ^ First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, § V, 212
  40. ^ First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, § V, 214
  41. ^ Balanovskiy, Valentin (2018). "What is Kant's Transcendental Reflection?". Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy. 75: 17–27. doi:10.5840/wcp232018751730. ISBN 978-1-63435-038-9.
  42. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 136
  43. ^ Entities that are known sub specie æternitatis (out of time, not through the form of time) do not have the predicate (Greek: Κατηγορίαι Katēgoriai) of reality. Some examples are Plato’s Ideas, religious gods, undead souls, Parmenides’ One, Spinoza’s Substance, Sherlock Holmes (it is always eighteen ninety-five), etc.
  44. ^ "The schema is not an image, because the image is a product of the reproductive imagination, while the schema of sensible concepts (also of figures in space) is a product of the pure a priori capacity to imagine…" (Umberto Eco, Kant and the Platypus, Harcourt, 1999, § 2.5). Eco compared a Kantian schema to Peano axioms, Wittgenstein's concept of Bild (a proposition that has the same "form" as the fact that it represents), and a computer programming flowchart. In this way, it is a procedural rule that provides instructions regarding the construction of a sensible intuition from an abstract, general concept. See also Diego Marconi, Lexical Competence, MIT Press, 1997, pp. 146 ff.
  45. ^ Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, "Editor's Introduction," Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1950, p. xvii.
  46. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 143
  47. ^ a b William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 43.
  48. ^ William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 43 f.
  49. ^ a b c d William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 44.
  50. ^ William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p.44.
  51. ^ a b William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 45.
  52. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 145
  53. ^ Kant's Critical Philosophy for English Readers, John P. Mahaffy, Note to page 263.
  54. ^ a b c d Walsh, W.H., "Schematism"
  55. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 146
  56. ^ Howard Caygill, A Kant Dictionary, "Schema(tism)"
  57. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 147. Note:By function, Kant means "… the unity of the act of ordering various representations under a common representation." — Critique of Pure Reason, A 68
  58. ^ Justus Hartnack, Kant’s Theory of Knowledge (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1967), 4, p. 102 f., “…there is nothing empirical that corresponds to these ideas….The transcendent ideas serve only as conditions of making inferences from the conditioned to the unconditioned….There are three kinds of such inferences: (1) paralogisms (inferences concerning the idea of a [immortal] soul; (2) antinomies (inferences concerning the idea of a [deterministic] world); and (3) the idea of pure reason (inferences concerning the idea of God).”
  59. ^ a b Kant, A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Robert Paul Wolff (New York: Anchor Books, 1967), “Schematism,” W. H. Walsh, p. 83.
  60. ^ a b Kant, A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Robert Paul Wolff, “Schematism,” W. H. Walsh, p. 83-4.
  61. ^ (Kant, A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Robert Paul Wolff, “Schematism,” W. H. Walsh, pp. 83-5)
  62. ^ According to Plato, there are two spheres of being: intelligible and sensible. There is “…an intelligible world of many self-existent Forms or Ideas, apprehended by reason only – and a sensible world of particular objects, each participating in one or more of these Forms or Ideas." George Grote, Plato, and the Other Companions of Sokrates (London: John Murray, 1888), volume III of IV, ch. XXVII, “Parmenides,” p.59.
  63. ^ Frank Thilly and Ledger Wood, A History of Philosophy (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966), Part One, III, 9, “Doctrine of Ideas,” p. 80, “…the relation between a particular and the form which it exemplifies is called ‘participation’….”
  64. ^ Diogenes Laërtius. Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1972), volume I, Book III, 13, “…the things within our experience bear the same names as those ideas because they partake of them….”
  65. ^ Diogenes Laërtius. Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1972), volume I, Book III, 13, “…Plato says that they [the ideas] stand in nature like archetypes, and that all things else bear a resemblance to the ideas because they are copies of these archetypes.”
  66. ^ Frank Thilly and Ledger Wood, A History of Philosophy (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston), 1966, Part One, III, 9, “Doctrine of Ideas,” p. 80.
  67. ^ "Introduction," I, c.
  68. ^ "unbewussten Vorstellungen"
  69. ^ "jenseits der Erkenntniss liegen"
  70. ^ "Vermittlung"
  71. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, B 291
  72. ^ Walsh, W.H., Schematism included in Kant: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Robert Paul Wolff, New York: Doubleday, 1967, p. 81
  73. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 10
  74. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, B 188 ff.
  75. ^ "It may be asked why Kant in this chapter [on schemata] so completely ignores space. No really satisfactory answer seems to present itself. (Norman Kemp Smith, A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, New York: Macmillan, 1918, p. 341)"
  76. ^ "…consciousness of time presupposes consciousness of space…."(Norman Kemp Smith, A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, New York: Macmillan, 1918, p. 341)
  77. ^ a b Norman Kemp Smith, A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, New York: Macmillan, 1918, p. 341
  78. ^ "It might be asked why Kant schematized the categories in terms of time only and not of space, since space was also both sensible and a priori. The answer is perhaps simply that the second method [that of using space] would not work out so well, for time seems essential for the formulation of any tolerably clear idea of substance or causality in a way in which space is not."(A. C. Ewing, A Short Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967, chapter IV, p. 146)
  79. ^ "…in a note written for his private use he proposes to schematize the categories in terms of space as well as time." (A. C. Ewing, A Short Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967, chapter IV, p. 146)
  80. ^ "…the nearest he ever came to this [schematization] was to add the words 'in space' to the definition of [the relational category of] community [reciprocity] in the second edition [of the Critique of Pure Reason B 256]."(A. C. Ewing, A Short Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967, chapter IV, p. 146)
  81. ^ A. C. Ewing refers to the category of community as "…a two-sided relation between different co-existing substances…." (A. C. Ewing, A Short Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967, chapter IV, p. 166) He relates that particular category to space as its transcendental schema. He wrote that "…except under spatial conditions we cannot conceive how different substances could interact…." (p. 175) and "…before we can apply it [the category of community or reciprocity] we must understand it in terms of space…." (p. 175)
  82. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 832
  83. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 834
  84. ^ Prolegomena to any future metaphysics, § 34
  85. ^ Kant, Notes and Fragments, Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. 394, 18:686
  86. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant–Studien, Band 49 (1957), Kölner Universitäts–Verlag
  87. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Critique of the Kantian Philosophy", Courier Dover Publications, 2012, p. 450
  88. ^ "…from the chapter on the schematism of the pure concepts of the understanding (a chapter which, in spite of all our respect for Kant, we must call an audacious piece of nonsense) it is very clear that these categories not only contribute nothing towards intuitive perception, but are very far removed from this, since there are still to be found between them and intuitive perception these quite peculiar absurdities, the schemata." Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Vol. 2, "Against Kant," p. 466.
  89. ^ "There is … inserted between the categories and intuitive perception the schema, an absurdity whose non–existence is plain to anyone in his senses…." Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Vol. 2, "Against Kant," p. 472.
  90. ^ Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Vol. 2, "Against Kant," pp. 466-7.
  91. ^

    …here more than anywhere else do the intentional nature of Kant's method of procedure and the resolve, arrived at beforehand, to find what would correspond to the analogy, and what might assist the architectonic symmetry, clearly come to light. … By assuming schemata of the pure (void of content) concepts a priori of the understanding (categories) analogous to the empirical schemata (or representatives of our actual concepts through the imagination), he overlooks the fact that the purpose of such schemata is here entirely wanting. The purpose of the schemata in the case of empirical (actual) thinking is related solely to the material content of such concepts. Since these concepts are drawn from empirical perception, we assist ourselves and see where we are, in the case of abstract thinking, by casting now and then a fleeting, retrospective glance at perception from which the concepts are taken, in order to assure ourselves that our thinking still has real content. This, however, necessarily presupposes that the concepts which occupy us have sprung from perception…. But with concepts a priori, which have no content at all, obviously this is of necessity omitted because these have not sprung from perception, but come to it from within, in order first to receive a content from it.

    — The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1, Courier Dover Publications, 2012, p. 450
  92. ^ Lectures on Modern Idealism, Lecture II, p. 57
  93. ^ a b Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 53 f.
  94. ^ "It was not clear what the link was between categories and intuitions and how empty forms of the understanding could be applied to sensations. Kant was aware of this problem and tried to address it through the doctrine of the schematism, but his contemporaries were not able to follow him here. Indeed, the doctrine of the schematism was left largely out of consideration by Kant's critics." Kant's Early Critics, Edited by Brigitte Sassen, Cambridge University Press, 2007, p. 30.
  95. ^ Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, Indiana U. Press, Bloomington, 1962, § 22. "The Transcendental Schematism," Page 111
  96. ^ McClelland, J.L., et al., Parallel Distributed Processing, Vol. 2, p. 17
  97. ^ Kant’s Theory of Knowledge: An Analytical Introduction, Georges Dicker, Oxford University Press, "Preface," p. viii.
  98. ^ A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (London: Macmillan, 1918), p. 334.
  99. ^ Quoted in The Spirit and the Uses of Mathematical Sciences, edited by Thomas L. Saaty and Fritz Joachim Weyl, "Insight and Reflection," p. 283, New York:McGraw-Hill, 1969.
  100. ^ A General and Introductory View of Professor Kant’s Principles Concerning Man, the World and the Deity, submitted to the Consideration of the Learned, Principle LVI, p.104 note.
  101. ^ difficult to interpret
  102. ^ The Review of Metaphysics, vol. 43, No. 1, September 1989, p. 107
  103. ^ The Cambridge Companion to Kant, edited by Paul Guyer, ch. 12, p. 368, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
  104. ^ However, according to Aristotle’s third man argument, there must be a mediator between any two mediated or connected things, including other mediators. This results in an infinite number of mediators.
  105. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 138
  106. ^ Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. I, Book I, Chapter I, § 4, Paragraph 35, Page 15. Peirce claimed that, at first, Kant severely distinguished between intuitive observation and discursive intellection. Later, Kant proposed that schemata connected the two separate cognitive processes.
  107. ^ a b Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. I, Book I, Chapter I, § 4, Paragraph 35, Page 15
  108. ^ a b c Walsh, W. H., "Schematism", Kant–Studien, Band 49 (1957)
  109. ^ A few such dichotomies are concept/sensuous intuition, intelligible/sensible, logic/aesthetic, formal/material, soul/body, understanding/sensation, ideal/real, intelligence/world, and a priori concept/intuition.
  110. ^ This is evident by the title of his inaugural dissertation of 1770 at age 46, "On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible World" (De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis).
  111. ^ "…Kant’s problem of intuition and understanding is an epistemic version of the Cartesian problem of getting body and mind together (with Kant’s Schema serving as a kind of methodological pineal gland….)," (Abraham P. Socher, The Radical Enlightenment of Solomon Maimon: Judaism, Heresy, and Philosophy, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2007, chapter 3, "German Idealism in a Maimonidean Key," p. 88 f.)
  112. ^ "Kant is struggling with the problem with which all philosophers find themselves confronted: how can what is sensed be also thought? What is the relation of the intelligible to the sensible in things?"(H. W. B. Joseph, Essays in Ancient & Modern Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1935, X, "The Schematism of the Categories in Kant’s Kritik of Pure Reason," p. 273)
  113. ^ Vide Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason and Other Works of the Theory of Ethics, Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott, Part I, Book I, ch. II, "Of the Typic of the Pure Practical Judgement," p. 159 ff. (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1898).
  114. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, Translated, with an Introduction, by Werner S. Pluhar, "Translator’s Introduction," 15, p. lxxxvi.
  115. ^ Sumangali Rajiva [1999]. "Kant’s Concept of Reflective Judgment," Doctoral Thesis, University of Toronto, p. 98 f.
  116. ^ Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, vol. I, Appendix, p. 470, New York: Dover Publications, 1969.
  117. ^ See Gotthard Ludwig Kosengarten’s letter of 4 June 1789 to Kant: “…der Typus…ist mir unbegreiflich….[the typus is incomprehensible to me….]”
  118. ^ Adam Westra, The Typic in Kant’s 'Critique of Practical Reason': Moral Judgment and Symbolic Representation, "Introduction," 2.1, p. 4, Berlin:De Gruyter, 2016.
  119. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, Translated, with an Introduction, by Werner S. Pluhar, "Translator’s Introduction," 15, p. lxxxvi.
  120. ^ Immanuel Kant, First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, 2, p. 8 (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), "…das Vermögen der Subsumtion des Besondern unter das Allgemeine …."
  121. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason A 138. "Now clearly there must be something that is a third, something that must be homogeneous with the Category, on the one hand, and with the phenomenon, on the other hand, and that this makes possible the application of the Category to the phenomenon. This mediating representation must be pure (i.e., without anything empirical), and yet must be both intellectual, on the one hand, and sensible, on the other hand. Such a representation is the Transcendental Schema."
  122. ^ Plato, "Parmenides." 132e - 133a. "…[N]othing can be like the Form, nor can the Form be like anything. Otherwise a second Form will always make its appearance over and above the first Form, and if that second Form is like anything, yet a third. And there will be no end to this emergence of fresh Forms, if the Form is to be like the thing that partakes of it."
  123. ^ Metaphysics 990b17–1079a13, 1039a2; Sophistic Refutations 178b36 ff.
  124. ^ Turnbull, Robert G., "The 'Third Man Argument' and the Text of the Parmenides" (1983). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 122. p. 18.
  125. ^ Norman Kemp Smith, A Commentary to Kant’s 'Critique of Pure Reason' , Part II, Division I, Book II, chapter 1, p. 335 (London: Macmillan, 1918)
  126. ^ Hylomorphism
  127. ^ Form and content
  128. ^ Norman Kemp Smith, A Commentary to Kant’s 'Critique of Pure Reason' , p. 335 f.
  129. ^ Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 54.
  130. ^ Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 55.
  131. ^ Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), Translator’s [Werner S. Pluhar] Introduction, 2. xxxvi.
  132. ^ a b c Schelling’s Transcendental Idealism, Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Co., 1892, Chapter I, p. 11.
  133. ^ Schelling’s Transcendental Idealism, Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Co., 1892, Chapter I, p. 15.
  134. ^ Schelling’s Transcendental Idealism, Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Co., 1892, Chapter I, p. 22 f.
  135. ^ Schelling’s Transcendental Idealism, Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Co., 1892, Chapter I, p. 11 f.
  136. ^ Schelling’s Transcendental Idealism, Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Co., 1892, Chapter I, p. 10.
  137. ^ The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason, pp. 147-172
  138. ^ Leahy, Robert L. (1996). Cognitive therapy : basic principles and applications. Northvale, N.J.: J. Aronson. ISBN 1-56821-850-8. OCLC 34354878.

Bibliography

edit