[go: up one dir, main page]

In intuitionistic logic, the Harrop formulae, named after Ronald Harrop, are the class of formulae inductively defined as follows:[1][2][3]

  • Atomic formulae are Harrop, including falsity (⊥);
  • is Harrop provided and are;
  • is Harrop for any well-formed formula ;
  • is Harrop provided is, and is any well-formed formula;
  • is Harrop provided is.

By excluding disjunction and existential quantification (except in the antecedent of implication), non-constructive predicates are avoided, which has benefits for computer implementation.

Discussion

edit

Harrop formulae are "well-behaved" also in a constructive context. For example, in Heyting arithmetic  , Harrop formulae satisfy a classical equivalence not generally satisfied in constructive logic:[1]

 

There are however  -statements that are  -independent, meaning these are simple   statements for which excluded middle is not  -provable. Indeed, while intuitionistic logic proves   for any  , the disjunction will not be Harrop.

Hereditary Harrop formulae and logic programming

edit

A more complex definition of hereditary Harrop formulae is used in logic programming as a generalisation of Horn clauses, and forms the basis for the language λProlog. Hereditary Harrop formulae are defined in terms of two (sometimes three) recursive sets of formulae. In one formulation:[4]

  • Rigid atomic formulae, i.e. constants   or formulae  , are hereditary Harrop;
  •   is hereditary Harrop provided   and   are;
  •   is hereditary Harrop provided   is;
  •   is hereditary Harrop provided   is rigidly atomic, and   is a G-formula.

G-formulae are defined as follows:[4]

  • Atomic formulae are G-formulae, including truth(⊤);
  •   is a G-formula provided   and   are;
  •   is a G-formula provided   and   are;
  •   is a G-formula provided   is;
  •   is a G-formula provided   is;
  •   is a G-formula provided   is, and   is hereditary Harrop.

History

edit

Harrop formulae were introduced around 1956 by Ronald Harrop and independently by Helena Rasiowa.[2] Variations of the fundamental concept are used in different branches of constructive mathematics and logic programming.

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b Dummett, Michael (2000). Elements of Intuitionism (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 227. ISBN 0-19-850524-8.
  2. ^ a b A. S. Troelstra; H. Schwichtenberg (27 July 2000). Basic proof theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-77911-1.
  3. ^ Ronald Harrop (1956). "On disjunctions and existential statements in intuitionistic systems of logic". Mathematische Annalen. 132 (4): 347–361. doi:10.1007/BF01360048. S2CID 120620003.
  4. ^ a b Dov M. Gabbay, Christopher John Hogger, John Alan Robinson, Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming: Logic programming, Oxford University Press, 1998, p 575, ISBN 0-19-853792-1