[go: up one dir, main page]

Jump to content

Walter Terence Stace

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from W. T. Stace)

Walter Terence Stace
Born(1886-11-17)17 November 1886[1][2]
London, UK
Died2 August 1967(1967-08-02) (aged 80)
Laguna Beach, California, US
OccupationPhilosopher, academic, civil servant
Alma materTrinity College Dublin
SubjectPhilosophy of mysticism
Notable worksMysticism and Philosophy (1960)

Walter Terence Stace (17 November 1886 – 2 August 1967) was a British civil servant, educator, public philosopher and epistemologist, who wrote on Hegel, mysticism, and moral relativism. He worked with the Ceylon Civil Service from 1910 to 1932, and from 1932 to 1955 he was employed by Princeton University in the Department of Philosophy. He is most renowned for his work in the philosophy of mysticism, and for books like Mysticism and Philosophy (1960) and Teachings of the Mystics (1960). These works have been influential in the study of mysticism, but they have also been severely criticised for their lack of methodological rigor and their perennialist pre-assumptions.

Early life and education

[edit]

Walter Terence Stace was born in Hampstead, London into an English military family. He was a son of Major Edward Vincent Stace (3 September 1841 – 6 May 1903) (of the Royal Artillery) and Amy Mary Watson (1856 - 29 March 1934), who were married on 21 December 1872 in Poona (Pune), India.[citation needed] In addition to attaining high rank in the Royal Artillery, Walter's father Edward had also served as a British Political Agent (February 1889-August 1893) in British Somaliland. Walter's great-grandfather William Stace (1755 - 31 May 1839) was Chief Commissary (Commissary-General) of the Royal Artillery during the Battle of Waterloo (18 June 1815).[3] Walter's mother Amy was a daughter of Rev. George Augustus Frederick Watson (1821-1897) and Elizabeth Mary Williams, who were married on 15 June 1852 in St. James' Church, Paddington, London. Rev. G. A. F. Watson was vicar (1877-1893) of St. Margaret's Church in Abbotsley, Huntingdonshire/Cambridgeshire.

Instead of pursuing a military career, Walter decided to follow a religious and philosophical path. He was educated at Bath College (1895-1901), Fettes College (in Edinburgh, Scotland) (1902-1904), and later at Trinity College Dublin (Ireland). His original intention was to become a priest in the Anglican Church, having experienced a religious conversion in his teens. However, while at Trinity College, through the influence of Hegel scholar Henry Stewart Macran (1867-1937) (professor of moral philosophy in Trinity College) he developed a deep interest in the systematic philosophy of G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831), and graduated in philosophy in 1908.[1][2]

Career

[edit]

Under family pressure Stace joined the British Civil Service, and between 1910 and 1932 he served in the Ceylon Civil Service (now Sri Lanka) which was then a part of the British Empire. He held several positions in the Ceylonese government, including District Judge (1919-1920) and Mayor of Colombo (1931-1932), the capital city of Ceylon. In Colombo a street named after him (Stace Road) still exists.

Stace Road in Colombo is named after the city's former mayor, W. T. Stace

It was during his period in Ceylon that he developed an interest in Hinduism and Buddhism, religions which were to influence his subsequent studies of mysticism. While employed by the Ceylon Civil Service, during the period 1920-1932 Stace published 4 philosophical works (see below).

Anticipating a change in the Ceylonese government and a possible termination of his employment, in 1929 Stace earned a LittD from Trinity College after he presented the college with a thesis, The Theory of Knowledge and Existence. In 1932 this thesis was published as a book by Oxford University Press. The LittD degree, and the 4 books he had published while an employee of the Ceylon Civil Service, proved to be the keys to his entry into a new career.

After being employed for 22 years (1910-1932) in the Ceylon Civil Service, in 1932 Stace was offered the option of retirement, which he took. He then moved to Princeton University (in Princeton, New Jersey, USA) where he was employed by the Department of Philosophy, first as lecturer in Philosophy (1932-1935) and then as Stuart Professor of Philosophy (1935-1955). In 1949-1950 he was president of the American Philosophical Association (Eastern Division).[4] Stace retired from Princeton University in 1955. From 1955 to 1967 he held the title/status of Professor Emeritus.[5]

Stace was married twice. His first wife, Adelaide McKechnie (born 1868 in Carlow, Ireland), was 18 years older. He married Adelaide in 1910 and they were divorced in 1924. His second wife was Blanche Bianca Beven (4 August 1897 – 17 July 1986), whom he married in 1926. Blanche was born in Colombo, Ceylon and died in Los Angeles County, California.

Walter Terence Stace died on 2 August 1967, of a heart attack at his home in Laguna Beach, California.[2][6]

Philosophy

[edit]

Stace's first 4 books - A Critical History of Greek Philosophy (1920), The Philosophy of Hegel: A Systematic Exposition (1924), The Meaning of Beauty (1929), and The Theory of Knowledge and Existence (1932) - were all published while he was employed by the Ceylon Civil Service. After these early works, his philosophy followed the British empiricist tradition of David Hume, G.E. Moore, Bertrand Russell and H.H. Price. However, for Stace, empiricism did not need to be confined to propositions which it is possible to demonstrate. Instead, our common sense beliefs find support in two empirical facts: (1) men's minds are similar (2) men co-operate with each other, with the aim of solving their common problems.[1]

Stace is regarded as a pioneer in the philosophical study of mysticism.[7] Many scholars regard Mysticism and Philosophy (1960) as his major work. Stace was the dissertation advisor of John Rawls when Rawls was a graduate student at Princeton, though it is not clear that he had a strong influence on Rawls. Richard Marius attributed his loss of faith partly to his intellectual engagement with Stace's essay Man Against Darkness.

Phenomenalist philosophy

[edit]

His work in the 1930s and 40s bears a strong influence of phenomenalism, a form of radical empiricism (not to be confused with phenomenology, which examines the structure and content of consciousness).[7] In his first book published while at Princeton, The Theory of Knowledge and Existence (1932), Stace proposes an empirical epistemology. He attempts to "trace out the logical steps by which the mind, starting with what is given, arrives at and justifies its belief in an external world".[8] The book can be seen as a criticism of pragmatism.[9] His paper Refutation of Realism (1934) acted as a response to G.E. Moore's famous refutation of idealism. Stace did not argue that realism is false, but that "there is absolutely no reason for asserting" it is true, so it "ought not be believed".[10] Turning from epistemology to ethics, in 1937 he considered whether morals were relative or subject to a general law in The Concept of Morals.

The public philosopher

[edit]

In 1948, Stace wrote an influential essay, Man Against Darkness, for The Atlantic Review in which he examined religion. He concluded that the spirit of scientific enquiry (rather than scientific discoveries themselves) has furthered religious scepticism by undermining the teleological presumption of an ultimate 'final cause'. Concern with divine purpose of events had been replaced by investigation into what had caused them; the new imaginative picture of the world was dominated by the idea that life is purposeless and meaningless. The effects of this change included moral relativity, the individualisation of morality, and the loss of belief in free will.[11] Stace wrote:

Skepticism did not have to wait for the discoveries of Darwin and the geologists in the nineteenth century. It flooded the world immediately after the age of the rise of science. Neither the Copernican hypothesis nor any of Newton's or Galileo's particular discoveries were the real causes. Religious faith might well have accommodated itself to the new astronomy. The real turning point between the medieval age of faith and the modern age of unfaith came when the scientists of the seventeenth century turned their backs upon what used to be called "final causes." ... If the scheme of things is purposeless and meaningless, then the life of man is purposeless and meaningless too. Everything is futile, all effort is in the end worthless. A man may, of course, still pursue disconnected ends, money, fame, art, science, and may gain pleasure from them. But his life is hollow at the center. Hence the dissatisfied, disillusioned, restless, spirit of modern man.

In the spring of 1949, the Massachusetts Institute of Technology hosted a forum called "The Social Implications of Scientific Progress—an Appraisal at Mid-Century."[12] Winston Churchill, Harry S. Truman, Vannevar Bush, Nelson Rockefeller were amongst those in attendance. Stace took part in a discussion called 'Science, Materialism and the Human Spirit' alongside J. Seelye Bixler (1894-1985), Percy W. Bridgman and Jacques Maritain. He contributed an essay, The Need for a Secular Ethic, in which he concluded that although supernatural or metaphysical justifications for morality are in decline, this should not lead to a crisis of the moral faith if it is remembered that 'morals have a perfectly firm and objective foundation in the human personality'.[13] In 1954, he gave the annual Howison Lecture in Philosophy at University of California, Berkeley, where he spoke on "Mysticism and Human Reason".[14]

In the fall of 1957, two years after retiring from his post at Princeton, Stace was involved in a controversy surrounding Dr. Joseph Hugh Halton (1913-1979), a member of the Roman Catholic Dominican Order (Order of Preachers) who was the Roman Catholic chaplain at Princeton University and the Director of the Aquinas Institute (located near the Princeton University campus). Halton criticised the university's 'abusive liberalism', and Stace was the first of those singled out for censure. Halton stated that 'Stace is enthroning the devil' and that he was 'professionally incompetent', while his philosophy was described as a 'metaphysical mambo'. The Princeton president Dr. Robert F. Goheen stripped Dr. Halton of his title, an action which was supported by Jacques Maritain, the noted Roman Catholic philosopher and theologian and former Princeton professor.[15]

Stace continued to engage with the public until the end of his career. Two of his final books, Religion and the Modern Mind (1952) and The Teachings of the Mystics (1960) were written for the general reader. He gave lectures at various university campuses around the United States, many of which were included in Man Against Darkness and other essays (1967).

Philosophy of religion and mysticism

[edit]

It is in the philosophy of mysticism that Stace is both important and influential, and his thought is at its most original. He has been described as "one of the pioneers in the philosophical study of mysticism", as someone who laid out and offered solutions to the major issues in the study of the subject, and created an important phenomenological classification of mystical experience.[7][16] Stace is seen as an important representative of the perennial philosophy (also known as the perennialism) that sees a universal core to religious feelings.[17][18] However, although he is seen by many scholars as an important thinker to acknowledge, he is also one to dispute.[7][note 1]

Stace's philosophy of mysticism grew out of his earlier empiricist epistemology, although this is something many critics of his position fail to appreciate.[7] The concept of the 'given', commonly used in phenomenalism to understand the nature of experience, is crucial to both his earlier epistemology and his later analysis. For Stace it lies at the basis of our knowledge of the external world and of ourselves. The given has an important epistemological function because it possesses the properties of certainty (infallibility, incorrigibility, indubitability), and it provides the ultimate justification for all forms of human knowledge. Stace's Theory of Knowledge and Existence (1932) explains that knowledge arises from the process of interpretation of the given, although he writes that it is not easy to distinguish between the given and interpretation of it. For Overall, the 'pure experience' or 'sensation' he refers to in Mysticism and Philosophy (1960) is the same as the given that he had been writing about earlier.

The 1952 books

[edit]

In 1952 Stace published three books about religion. Each examined the struggle between the religious worldview and those of science and of naturalism, which he had begun to explore in his essays Man Against Darkness and The Need for a Secular Ethic in the 1940s. Religion and the Modern Mind is divided into three sections, the first of these looks at the medieval "world-picture" which Stace characterises as marked by a religious, moral and purposeful view of existence. The second section looks at the modern world, which is characterised by the rise of science and naturalism (although Stace denies that the latter logically follows from the former), and the Romantic reaction to this. The final section looks specifically at religion and morality in the modern world. Stace examines religious truth and its expression, and concludes that the latter necessarily takes symbolic form in much the same way as he does in Time and Eternity. He also roots morality in both utilitarian considerations and in mysticism, which together fuse into "a single homogeneous set of ideal ends".[22]

The Gate of Silence is a 50-page poetic meditation upon religion and naturalism in which Stace expounds "the doctrine of the flatness of the world",[23] which is a world that is void of meaning, purpose and value, in which "the hogwash of spirituality"[24] will provide no solace. In his prefatory note Stace explains that he wrote the book four years previously and that it "records the phase of intellectual and emotional experience through which the writer was passing at the time."[25]

Stace called Time and Eternity a "defence of religion"[26] that also seeks to investigate how God can be both being and non-being. He roots the book in the ancient religious insight that "all religious thought and speech are through and through symbolic".[26] Addressing the apparent inconsistency between the book and the naturalism of Man Against Darkness, he maintains that he does not withdraw his naturalism by "a jot or a tittle",[26] but rather seeks "to add to it that other half of the truth which I now think naturalism misses."[26] In addition to the symbolic nature of all religious expression, the book proposes the existence of two realms of being, time and eternity, which intersect but do not contradict each other. According to the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, many consider this to be his most profound work.[27]

The 1960 books

[edit]

Stace published his two final books on religion in 1960. The Teachings of the Mystics (1960) was written for the general rather than academic reader. The book sets out a simplified version of his philosophy of religion found in Mysticism and Philosophy, and gives examples from writings of mystics (and occasionally from the scriptures of the world's principal religions) that illustrate his idea that mysticism is everywhere "the apprehension of an ultimate nonsensuous unity in all things".[28]

Mysticism and Philosophy (1960) is generally regarded both as Stace's key work and one that is the "standard point of departure"[29] in the critical study of mysticism. In it Stace explains that he writes as a philosopher, empiricist and analyst rather than mystic,[30] and that mystical experience can and should be distinguished from its interpretation.[31] He makes a distinctinction between extrovertive and introvertive mystical experience.[note 2] In the former, the mystic perceives the unity in "the multiplicity of external material objects", while in the latter the mystic perceives the One within the depths of her consciousness "as the wholly naked One devoid of any plurality whatever".[32] Stace also looks at whether mystical experience can be considered objective or subjective, and considers whether the relationship between God and the world should properly be considered pantheism, dualism or something else. He examines mysticism, logic and language, and concludes that the laws of logic do not apply to mysticism and that mystical experience is paradoxical but not ineffable (a development in his thought from Time and Eternity). Finally, Stace says he does not wish to be drawn into a battle of prejudices as to whether or not mysticism contributes to the moral good.

Stace summarised his thought on mysticism in two lectures given at Mount Holyoke College in 1961, entitled The Psychology of Mysticism and The Philosophy of Mysticism respectively.[33] In the former he states that the psychology of mysticism must rely on introspection, because it is the only method that is available to investigate the phenomenon, despite it being difficult to verify (unlike the inspection of physical events). Like William James, he distinguishes between ordinary and mystical consciousness; the former he describes as sensory-intellectual, while the latter contains neither sensory nor intellectual content. He then proceeds to layout the psychological qualities of mystical experience, which he roots in a passage from the Mandukya Upanishad:[34][note 3]

  1. Undifferentiated unity
  2. Dissolution of the self
  3. Feeling of revelation or veracity of the event
  4. Feeling of blessedness and peace
  5. Feeling of serenity
  6. The transformation of the subject's moral character from evil towards good and nobility.

Stace characterised his philosophy of mysticism as the examination of whether mystical experience is subjective or objective, that is whether it is imagined or real. Again he turns to the Mandukya Upanishad for his definition of mysticism, and identifies the realisation the personal self is identical with the infinite Self at the core of the experience. Although there are three causes for this (loss of individuality; transcending space and time; feeling of peace and bliss) these are not logical reasons. Further he holds that the unanimity of mystical experience across cultures is not an argument for its objectivity, as illusions can be found in all peoples and cultures. That mystical experience is found in all cultures indicates that it is a part of human nature. Next Stace asks how we can say if something is objective. He defines the most important criteria for determining objectivity as 'orderliness' - or keeping in order with the laws of nature - rather than verifiability. Mystical experience is neither orderly nor disorderly, so cannot be classed as either subjective or objective. Stace terms this "transsubjective" (because the notions of subjective and objective do not apply to the infinite).[38]

Influence

[edit]

Stace's schema of mystical experience formed the basis for the most commonly cited scale to measure reports of mystical experience, Ralph W. Hood's Mysticism-scale.[39]

Criticism

[edit]

Although Stace's work on mysticism received a positive response, it has also been criticised in the 1970s and 1980s, for its lack of methodological rigour and its perennialist pre-assumptions.[40][41][42][43][web 1] Major criticism came from Steven T. Katz in his influential series of publications on mysticism and philosophy,[note 4] and from Wayne Proudfoot in his Religious experience (1985).[44]

As early as 1961 the Times Literary Supplement was critical of Stace's scholarship:

Professor Stace seems to have no knowledge of any Indian language and his examples are drawn from what is most monistic in the Upanishads and other sacred writings, usually in a very free translation not notable for its accuracy or for its lack of bias.[45][note 5]

Moore (1973) gives an overview of criticisms of Stace. He notes that the positing of a "phenomenological identity in mystical experiences" is problematic, which leads to either non-descriptive statements, or to value-laden statements on mystical experiences. Moore doubts whether Stace phenomenology of mystical experience is sufficient.[46] Moore notes that Stace's quotations from mystical writings are brief, "often second-hand," and omitting the contexts of these quotations.[46] Stace's list of characteristics hardly represents the broad variety of mystical experiences described by mystics.[46] His "unitary consciousness" is only one characteristic, and not necessarily connected to illuminating insight.[47][note 6] According to Moore, Stace also thinks too lightly about the relation between experience and language, supposing that descriptions are phenomenologically straightforward and reliable.[48] Stace is also normative in his preference for monistic mysticism and his rejection of theistic mysticism.[48][note 7] Moore concludes by noting that Stace fails to understand the difference between phenomenology and metaphysics, and that his writings don't provide solutions to the philosophical problems which mystical claims raise.[48]

Masson & Masson (1976) note that Stace starts with a "buried premise," namely that mysticism can provide truths about the world which cannot be obtained with science or logical thinking.[51] According to Masson & Masson, this premise makes Stace naive in his approach, and which is not accord with his self-presentation as an objective and empirical philosopher.[51] According to Masson & Masson, Stace fails in presenting mystical experiences as an objective source of information. They question Stace's exclusion of trances and other phenomena from his investigations, noting that such phenomena are an essential part of many descriptions of mystical experiences.[52] They give the example of Ramakrishna, a 19th-century Indian mystic, who is presented without a critical consideration of the sources.[50] They further note that Ramakrishna had delusions, a fact which they deem problematic for the use of Ramakrishna as a prime example of mystical consciousness.[53][note 8] They further note that Stace seems to be unaware of the major relevant scholarly studies on mysticism at the time of his writings.[54] According to Masson & Masson, Stace's criteria for inclusion and exclusion of cases are based on personal preferences,[55] and "his work reads more like a theological text than a philosophical one."[56]

According to Katz (1978), Stace's typology is "too reductive and inflexible," reducing the complexities and varieties of mystical experience into "improper categories."[57] According to Katz, Stace does not notice the difference between experience and interpretation of experience, and Stace fails to notice the epistemological issues involved in "mystical" experiences,[58] especially the fundamental epistemological issue of which conceptual framework precedes and shapes these experiences.[59] Katz further notes that Stace supposes that similarities in descriptive language also imply a similarity in experience, an assumption which Katz rejects.[60] According to Katz, close examination of the descriptions and their contexts reveals that those experiences are not identical.[61] Katz further notes that Stace held one specific mystical tradition to be superior and normative,[62] whereas Katz rejects reductionist notions and leaves God as God, and Nirvana as Nirvana.[63]

In defense of Stace, Hood (2001) cites Forman, who argues that introverted mysticism is correctly conceptualized as a common core, since it lacks all content, and is the correct basis for a perennial philosophy.[64][note 9] Hood notes that Stace's work is a conceptual approach, based on textual studies.[44] He posits his own work as a parallel approach, based on an empirical approach, thereby placing the conceptual claims in an empirical framework,[65] assuming that Stace is correct in his approach.[66] Jacob van Belzen (2010) criticized Hood, noting that Hood validated the existence of a common core in mystical experiences, but based on a conceptual framework which presupposes the existence of such a common core:

[T]he instrument used to verify Stace's conceptualization of Stace is not independent of Stace, but based on him."[43]

Belzen also notes that religion does not stand on its own, but is embedded in a cultural context, and this should be taken into account.[67] To this criticism Hood et al. answer that universalistic tendencies in religious research "are rooted first in inductive generalizations from cross-cultural consideration of either faith or mysticism,"[68] stating that Stace sought out texts which he recognized as an expression of mystical expression, from which he created his universal core. Hood therefore concludes that Belzen "is incorrect when he claims that items were presupposed."[68][note 10]

Shear (2011) notes that Stace regarded extroverted mysticism to be a less complete form of mysticism, but was puzzled by the fact that there are far more descriptions of introverted mysticism than of extroverted mysticism.[71] Shear proposes a developmental sequence of three higher states of consciousness:[72]

  1. the recognition of pure consciousness/emptiness
  2. the stable presence of this pure consciousness/emptiness throughout all activity
  3. the recognition of this pure consciousness/emptiness as the ground of all being

According to Shear, HS1 corresponds to Stace's introverted mysticism, whereas HS3 corresponds to Stace's extroverted mysticism, and is actually the more developed form of mysticism, in contrast to what Stace supposed.[71]

Works

[edit]
  • A Critical History of Greek Philosophy (1920) Online text
  • The Philosophy of Hegel: A Systematic Exposition (1924) Online text
  • The Meaning of Beauty (1929)
  • The Theory of Knowledge and Existence (1932)
  • The Concept of Morals (1937)
  • The Nature of the World. An Essay in Phenomenalist Metaphysics (1940)
  • The Destiny of Western Man (1942)[73]
  • What are Our Values? (Lincoln, Neb.: University of Nebraska Press, 1950)
  • Religion and the Modern Mind (1952)
  • Time and Eternity (Princeton: University Press, 1952)
  • Mysticism and Philosophy (1960) Full text online
  • Teachings of the Mystics (1960)
  • Man Against Darkness, and Other Essays (1967)

See also

[edit]

Explanatory notes

[edit]
  1. ^ One of the key opponents of Stace's philosophy and psychology of mysticism is Steven T. Katz, who proposed that there is no such thing as an unmediated mystical experience. Known as 'constructivism', this position holds that all states of mind are in some degree constructed by social and cultural factors, so that we cannot speak of a unitary consciousness.[19][20][21]
  2. ^ For extroverted mysticism, Stace gives a total of seven quotes from six persons. For introverted mysticism, Stace gives twenty-seven quotes from fifteen persons and texts.
  3. ^ The Mandukya Upanishad discusses the sacred syllable Om and the four states of consciousness (waking, dream, dreamless sleep, and Moksha or liberation). Stace refers to it in The Teachings of the Mystics and Mysticism and Philosophy, in addition to The Psychology of Mysticism. In each case he quotes from the twelfth and final paragraph, which describes Moksha, or the mystical experience. It is in Mysticism and Philosophy that the most complete excerpt is found: "The Fourth [state], say the wise… is not the knowledge of the senses, nor is it relative knowledge, nor yet inferential knowledge. Beyond the senses, beyond the understanding, beyond all expression, it is the Fourth. It is the pure unitary consciousness, wherein awareness of the world and of multiplicity is completely obliterated. It is ineffable peace. It is the Supreme good. It is One without a second. It is the Self."[35][36][37]
  4. ^ * Mysticism and Philosophical Analysis (Oxford University Press, 1978)
    * Mysticism and Religious Traditions (Oxford University Press, 1983)
    * Mysticism and Language (Oxford University Press, 1992)
    * Mysticism and Sacred Scripture (Oxford University Press, 2000)
  5. ^ Times Literary Supplement, 15 December 1961. p.901; quoted by Masson & Masson (1976) p.118.[45]
  6. ^ Moore refers to Buddhist enlightenment or prajna, an essential element in the Buddhist teachings, which has an uneasy relationship with dhyana, c.q. meditation, the other essential element of the Buddhist teachings. See dhyana and insight, and Bronkhorst, Johannes (1993), The Two Traditions Of Meditation In Ancient India, Motilal Banarsidass Publ.
  7. ^ For a similar distortion in perception, see Sweetman, Will (December 2004), "The prehistory of Orientalism: Colonialism and the Textual Basis for Bartholomaus Ziegenbalg's Account of Hinduism" (PDF), New Zealand Journal of Asian Studies, 6 (2): 12–38, archived from the original (PDF) on 7 February 2013, retrieved 21 November 2015{{citation}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link), and King, Richard (1999), Orientalism and Religion: Post-Colonial Theory, India and "The Mystic East", Routledge, who describe how Western preferences for monotheism influenced the Western perception of Indian religions, and the influence of their Brahmana informants, lead to a favoring of Advaita Vedanta as the quintessential Indian philosophy. This Advaitic preference, together with the influence of Unitarian missionaries, shaped the worldview of Swami Vivekananda, arguably one of the strongest forces in the shaping of the Western popular understanding of Indian "mysticism."[49] His Ramakrishna Mission spread his idiosyncratic understanding on Advaita Vedanta in the West, and popularized Ramakrishna, one of Stace's examples of genuine mystics,[50] as an exemplary Indian saint.
  8. ^ Ramakrishna may have suffered from temporal lobe epilepsy; see also List of people with epilepsy#Religious figures.
  9. ^ According to critics, Forman over-emphasizes the centrality of what he calls "pure conscious events" in mystical traditions, and also misunderstands its meaning in those traditions.[web 1]
  10. ^ Robert Sharf has criticised the idea that religious texts describe individual religious experience. According to Sharf, their authors go to great lengths to avoid personal experience, which would be seen as invalidating the presumed authority of the historical tradition.[69][70]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c Smith, James Ward (1967). "Walter Terence Stace 1886-1967". Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. 41: 136–138. JSTOR 3129280.
  2. ^ a b c W. T. Stace Britannica.com.
  3. ^ William Stace (1755 - 31 May 1839) was Chief Commissary (Commissary-General) of the Royal Artillery from 8 November 1810 – 30 April 1823, then the Royal Artillery promoted him and on 1 May 1823 he began serving as Royal Ordnance Storekeeper at Woolwich Arsenal. See: General W. H. Askwith (Colonel-Commandant Royal Artillery) - List of Officers of the Royal Regiment of Artillery from the Year 1716 to the Year 1899 (Fourth Edition) (London and Beccles: Printed by William Clowes and Sons, Limited for the Royal Artillery Institution, 1900), p. 194.
  4. ^ APA Divisional Presidents and Addresses (accessed 16 June 2014).
  5. ^ Princeton University | Department of Philosophy | Our History
  6. ^ "DR. WALTER STACE, PHILOSOPHER, DIES; Author of Hegel Study Was Professor at Princeton". New York Times. 5 August 1967.
  7. ^ a b c d e Overall, Christine, (1982) Mysticism, Phenomenalism and W.T. Stace. Charles S. Peirce Society, Transactions, 18:2
  8. ^ Stace, W. T., The Theory of Knowledge and Existence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932), p. 27.
  9. ^ F.C.S. Schiller Mind 1933 XLII(165):94–100
  10. ^ Brown, Patterson (March 1971). "Stace's Refutation of Realism". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 31 (3): 426–428. doi:10.2307/2105723. JSTOR 2105723.
  11. ^ Stace, W.T. (1967) Man Against Darkness and Other Essays, p. 15, University of Pittsburgh Press
  12. ^ Burchard, John Ely ed. (1950) Mid-Century: The Social Implications of Scientific Progress. Verbatim Account of the Discussions Held at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology on the Occasion of Its Mid-Century Convocation, 31 March 1 and 2 April 1949, Technology Press and Wiley, ASIN B000ES40E0
  13. ^ Bridgman, Percy W.; Bixler, Julius S.; Stace, Walter T.; Maritain, Jacques (June 1949). "Science, Materialism, and the Human Spirit". Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists. 5 (6–7): 192–200. Bibcode:1949BuAtS...5f.192B. doi:10.1080/00963402.1949.11457079.
  14. ^ Howison Lectures in Philosophy
  15. ^ Princeton furor over a chaplain Life Magazine, 7 October 1957, Vol. 43, No. 15, P. 137, ISSN 0024-3019
  16. ^ Hood. Ralph, W. (2001) Dimensions of Mystical Experiences: Empirical Studies and Psychological Links. Rodopi. p. 156 ISBN 978-9-04-201339-1
  17. ^ Leeming, David A. Madden, Kathryn. Marlan, Stanton. (Oct 2009) Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion: L-Z, Springer Science & Business Media. p.912.
  18. ^ Sharf, Robert H. Experience in Taylor, Mark C. (ed.) (2008) Critical Terms for Religious Studies. University of Chicago Press. pps. 95-96
  19. ^ Kelly, Edward F, and Grosso, Michael. (2010). Mystical Experience: Steven Katz and the Constructivist Backlash in Irreducible Mind: Toward a Psychology for the 21st Century, Rowman & Littlefield. p. 511 ISBN 9781442202061
  20. ^ Mysticism - 6. Constructivism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  21. ^ Bush, Stephen S. (2014). Visions of Religion: Experience, Meaning, and Power, Oxford University Press. p. 75-76 & 134 ISBN 9780199387410
  22. ^ Stace, W.T. Religion and the Modern Mind. Lippincott, 1952, p. 262.
  23. ^ Stace, W.T. The Gate of Silence. Beacon Press, 1952, p. 7.
  24. ^ Stace. The Gate of Silence. p. 34
  25. ^ Stace. The Gate of Silence. p. vii.
  26. ^ a b c d Stace, W.T. Time and Eternity: An Essay in the Philosophy of Religion. Princeton University Press, 1952, p. VI
  27. ^ Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2001-2006. Macmillan Reference USA
  28. ^ Stace, Walter Terence (1960), The Teachings of the Mystics, p. 14, New American Library, ISBN 0-451-60306-0
  29. ^ L. Philip Barnes. Walter Stace's Philosophy of Mysticism. Hermathena, No. 153 (Winter 1992), pp. 5-20.
  30. ^ Stace, Walter Terence. Mysticism and Philosophy. MacMillan, 1960, p. 6.
  31. ^ Stace. Mysticism and Philosophy. 1960, p. 32.
  32. ^ Stace. Mysticism and Philosophy. 1960, pps. 61-62.
  33. ^ Published in Man Against Darkness and Other Essays, University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967.
  34. ^ Stace, W. T. (1961). The Psychology of Mysticism in Man Against Darkness and Other Essays, University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967.
  35. ^ Stace, W. T. (1961). The Psychology of Mysticism in Man Against Darkness and Other Essays. p.24. University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967.
  36. ^ Stace, Walter Terence (1960), The Teachings of the Mystics. p. 20, New American Library, ISBN 0-451-60306-0
  37. ^ Stace, Walter Terence. Mysticism and Philosophy. p.88 MacMillan, 1960.
  38. ^ Stace, W. T. (1961). The Philosophy of Mysticism in Man Against Darkness and Other Essays, University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967.
  39. ^ Hood. Ralph, W. (2001) p. 156
  40. ^ Moore 1973, p. 148-150.
  41. ^ Masson & Masson 1976.
  42. ^ Katz 1978, p. 22-32.
  43. ^ a b Belzen 2010, p. 97.
  44. ^ a b Hood 2001, p. 32.
  45. ^ a b Masson & Masson 1976, p. 118.
  46. ^ a b c Moore 1973, p. 149.
  47. ^ Moore 1973, p. 149-150.
  48. ^ a b c Moore 1973, p. 150.
  49. ^ De Michelis 2005.
  50. ^ a b Masson & Masson 1976, p. 112-114.
  51. ^ a b Masson & Masson 1976, p. 110.
  52. ^ Masson & Masson 1976, p. 112, 121.
  53. ^ Masson & Masson 1976, p. 114.
  54. ^ Masson & Masson 1976, p. 115-116.
  55. ^ Masson & Masson 1976, p. 116-117.
  56. ^ Masson & Masson 1976, p. 117.
  57. ^ Katz 1978, p. 25.
  58. ^ Katz 1978, p. 28.
  59. ^ Katz 1978, p. 30.
  60. ^ Katz 1978, p. 46-47.
  61. ^ Katz 1978, p. 53-54.
  62. ^ Katz 1978, p. 65.
  63. ^ Katz 1978, p. 66.
  64. ^ Hood 2001, p. 32-33.
  65. ^ Hood 2001, p. 33.
  66. ^ Hood 2001, p. 33-34.
  67. ^ Belzen 2010, p. 50.
  68. ^ a b Hood et al. 2015, p. 467.
  69. ^ Sharf 1995.
  70. ^ Sharf 2000.
  71. ^ a b Shear 2011, p. 146 note 4.
  72. ^ Shear 2011, p. 144.
  73. ^ For a review see, for example [1] by W. Cerf, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 3, No. 3. (Mar. 1943), pp. 377–380.

Sources

[edit]

Printed sources

[edit]
  • Belzen, Jacob van (2010), Towards Cultural Psychology of Religion: Principles, Approaches, Applications, Springer Science & Business Media
  • Hood, Ralph W. (1975), "The Construction and Preliminary Validation of a Measure of Reported Mystical Experience", Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 14 (1): 29–41, doi:10.2307/1384454, JSTOR 1384454, S2CID 147200008
  • Hood, Ralph W. (2001), Dimensions of Mystical Experiences: Empirical Studies and Psychological Links, Rodopi
  • Hood, Ralph W.; Streib, Heinz; Keller, Barbara; Klein, Constantin (2015), "The Contribution of the Study of "Spirituality" to the Psychology of Religion: Conclusions and Future Prospects", in Sreib, Heinz; Hood, Ralph W. (eds.), Semantics and Psychology of Spirituality: A Cross-Cultural Analysis, Springer
  • Katz, Steven T. (1978), "Language, Epistemology, and Mysticism", in Katz, Steven T. (ed.), Mysticism and Philosophical Analysis, Oxford university Press
  • Masson, J. Moussaieff; Masson, T.C. (1976), "The Study of Mysticism: A Criticism of W.T. Stace", Journal of Indian Philosophy, 4 (1–2): 109–125, doi:10.1007/bf00211109, S2CID 170168616
  • De Michelis, Elizabeth (2005), A History of Modern Yoga, Continuum
  • Moore, Peter G. (1973), "Recent Studies of Mysticism: A Critical Survey", Religion, 3 (2): 146–156, doi:10.1016/0048-721x(73)90005-5
  • Sharf, Robert H. (1995), "Buddhist Modernism and the Rhetoric of Meditative Experience" (PDF), NUMEN, 42 (3): 228–283, doi:10.1163/1568527952598549, hdl:2027.42/43810
  • Sharf, Robert H. (2000), "The Rhetoric of Experience and the Study of Religion" (PDF), Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7 (11–12): 267–87
  • Shear, Jonathan (2011), "Eastern approaches to altered states of consciousness", in Cardeña, Etzel; Michael, Michael (eds.), Altering Consciousness: Multidisciplinary Perspectives, ABC-CLIO

Web-sources

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]